Hide table of contents

Consider one billion animals. Now consider one trillion animals. The second number is vastly higher. However, it is difficult for many people to have a clear idea of what the magnitude of that difference is. As a result of this, we often fail to assess properly what we should do when large numbers of individuals are affected.

This is due to a cognitive bias called scope insensitivity. It is also known as scope neglect. It means we don’t realize the real scope of a certain quantity. So when we compare two different quantities we fail to notice the difference between them. This usually happens when those quantities are very large.

Scope insensitivity causes people not to adjust their valuation of an issue in proportion to the size or scale of it.[1] Scope insensitivity especially impairs our judgments about helping animals because of the massive amount of animal suffering and death.

Scope insensitivity probably occurs due to our inability to visualize, or otherwise imagine, such large numbers. When we are not able to visualize a situation where a large number of individuals need our help, we must instead understand it at a more abstract quantitative level. This rarely triggers a strong emotional reaction in us, such as we get when we help a particular number of individuals we can visualize. Importantly from an ethical standpoint, it has been argued that too little emotional involvement can lead to a failure to react.[2] Because of that, scope insensitivity may contribute to non-optimal decision outcomes in situations where the goal is to improve the situation of as many individuals as possible.[3] In fact, sometimes those decisions are very poor ones.

An example: how much would you be willing to pay to save a certain number of animals?

In the original study that assessed this phenomenon, different groups of people were asked how much they would pay to save either a group of 2,000 birds, another of 20,000 birds, or a group of 200,000 birds from drowning in ponds polluted with oil. Assuming people’s intention was truly to help as many birds as possible, they should value each of their lives equally. If they were looking clearly at the issue, we would expect them to be willing to pay 10 times as much for the second group as for the first group, and 100 times as much for the third group as for the first group. In fact, the results showed that willingness to pay did not increase in proportion with the number of birds saved.[4]  Participants were willing to pay $80 to save 2,000 birds. They were willing to pay $78 to save 20,000. That is, 2$ less to save 18,000 more individuals. Finally, they were willing to pay $88 to save 200,000. Thus, only 8$ extra to help 180,000 more birds. That suggests that participants valued each individual bird less the more of them there were to save (4, 0.39, and 0.044 cents, respectively).

This is a clear case of scope insensitivity. The fact that participants were only willing to pay $80 to save a group of 2,000 birds is very problematic in its own right. Yet, the scope insensitivity they showed is also worrisome, given how it impairs our moral judgment when confronted when very large numbers of individuals in need of our help.

A psychological explanation of the scope insensitivity bias

One explanation of how scope insensitivity occurs has to do with how we often represent things in order to understand them, which is called representativeness heuristic (heuristics, often referred to as “mental shortcuts,” are ways to easily solve problems, especially when we have to make a decision). The representativeness heuristic describes people’s tendency to imagine a simple, normal example of the type of problem being presented to them, rather than picturing all the specific details of the case in question, which may be very complex. Like all heuristics, this can be a useful mental shortcut, since it reduces problems to a more manageable size, thereby simplifying our information processing and decision-making efforts.

However, as the example above shows, this mechanism can be inappropriate to use in many situations. In the example, people tended to imagine or visualize roughly the same thing, so their natural empathy was stimulated to roughly the same degree by all of them, despite the significant differences in the three numbers.[5]

If a person’s aim is to feel good, or to avoid feeling bad, through some altruistic behavior (like a charitable donation), they do not have an incentive to check whether they are actually doing some good or just seeming to do so – because it feels the same in each case and that is their bottom line.[6] In addition, being confronted with too much suffering can lead to what is often called the collapse of compassion, a defense mechanism that reduces or eliminates our sensitivity to the harms others suffer when we are faced with massive amounts of suffering.[7] As a result, people will tend not to do the cognitive work of adjusting for scope neglect.

That being said, part of the problem may consist in people simply failing to notice their bias, meaning that they would adjust their decisions if only they were informed about its existence.[8]

In addition, due to the key role of emotions in moral intuitions and in decision-making processes,[9] it has been shown that raising emotional concern for individual victims of large-scale suffering increases overall concern. It has also been shown that personal stories and visual images motivate helping responses more than using abstract numerical figures and statistics. These vivid descriptions of single individuals in need can be useful to keep emotions aroused when large numbers of individuals are concerned.[10] This is a way of trying to adjust advocacy to the existence of cognitive biases. It is problematic, however, as we are not always going to be able to do this. For instance, we may not be able to provide such stories when we consider possible new forms of suffering in the future.

Scope insensitivity and our failure to help animals in the wild in need of aid

Scope insensitivity is especially problematic when it biases us away from helping animals in the wild. There is an astronomical amount of suffering constantly going on in the natural world. For example, the leading estimate as to the number of insects in the wild is 1018.[11] A majority of these animals die a painful death in their first days of life. This amount of suffering simply dwarfs any that we are used to dealing with or thinking about.

In order to react properly to these magnitudes, we should be prepared to adjust our initial emotional reaction based on our more abstract understanding of the quantity. For example, we can try to imagine the largest number of insects that we can and then try to remember how much bigger of an issue it is than we can possibly imagine.

Giving everyone equal consideration

The equivalent suffering of each individual should be given the same consideration. Unfortunately, however, the valuations of individual lives and suffering are often guided by moral intuitions which are highly influenced by non-rational mechanisms and emotions that can lead to partial judgments. As we have seen here, one of these mechanisms is scope insensitivity.

Hence, we cannot rely solely on our more immediate decision-making processes when making moral judgments involving large numbers of individuals. We must bear this in mind and try to adjust for the errors our decision-making process will run into because of this bias.


Further readings

Baron, J. & Greene, J. (1996) “Determinants of insensitivity to quantity in valuation of public goods: Contribution, warm glow, budget constraints, availability, and prominence”, Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied, 2, pp. 107-125.

Bruers, S. (2016) “A rational approach to improve worldwide well-being”, The Rational Ethicist, februari 12 [accessed on 20 May 2017].

Bruers, S. (2017) “Moral illusions and wild animal suffering neglect”, The Rational Ethicist, juli 20 [accessed on 18 May 2017].

Cameron, C. D. & Payne, B. K. (2011) “Escaping affect: How motivated emotion regulation creates insensitivity to mass suffering”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 100, pp. 1-15.

Carson, R. T. & Mitchell, R. C. 1995) “Sequencing and nesting in contingent valuation surveys”, Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 28, pp. 155-173.

Desmeules, R.; Bechara, A. & Dubé, L. (2008) “Subjective valuation and asymmetrical motivational systems: Implications of scope insensitivity for decision making”, Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 21, pp. 211-224.

Dickert, S.; Västfjäll, D.; Kleber, J. & Slovic, P. (2015) “Scope insensitivity: The limits of intuitive valuation of human lives in public policy”, Journal of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition, 4, pp. 248-255 [accessed on 16 May 2017].

Erick, S. F. & Fischhoff, B. (1998) “Scope (in)sensitivity in elicited valuations”, Risk Decision and Policy, 3, pp. 109-123.

Fetherstonhaugh, D.; Slovic, P.; Johnson, S. & Friedrich, J. (1997) “Insensitivity to the value of human life: A study of psychophysical numbing”, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 14, pp. 238-300.

Kogut, T.; Slovic, P. & Västfjäll, D. (2015) “Scope insensitivity in helping decisions: Is it a matter of culture and values?”, Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 144, pp. 1042-1052.


This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Notes

  1. ^

    Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A. (eds.) (2000) Choices, values and frames, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  2. ^

    Small, D. A.; Loewenstein, G. & Slovic, P. (2007) “Sympathy and callousness: The impact of deliberative thought on donations to identifiable and statistical victims”, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 102, pp. 143-153.

  3. ^

    Baron, J. & Szymanska, E. (2011) “Heuristics and biases in charity”, in Oppenheimer, D.M. & Olivola, C. Y. (eds.) The science of giving: Experimental approaches to the study of charity, New York: Psychology Press, pp. 215-235.

  4. ^

    Kahneman, D.; Ritov, I.; Schkade, D.; Sherman, S. J. & Varian, H. R. (1999) “Economic preferences or attitude expressions?: An analysis of dollar responses to public issues”, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 19, pp. 203-235.

  5. ^

    Hsee, C. K. & Rottenstreich, Y. (2004) “Music, Pandas, and Muggers: On the Affective Psychology of Value”, Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 133, pp. 23-30.

  6. ^

    Dickert, S.; Västfjäll, D.; Kleber, J. & Slovic, P. (2012) “Valuations of human lives: Normative expectations and psychological mechanisms of (ir)rationality”, Synthese, 189, suppl. 1, pp. 95-105.

  7. ^

    Slovic, P. (2007) “‘If I look at the mass I will never act’: Psychic numbing and genocide”, Judgment and Decision Making Journal, 2, pp. 79-95 [accessed on 15 May 2017].

  8. ^

    Caviola, L.; Faulmüller, N.; Everett, J. A. C.; Savulescu, J. & Kahane, G. (2014) “The evaluability bias in charitable giving: Saving administration costs or saving lives?”, Judgment and Decision Making, 9, pp. 303-315 [accessed on 9 May 2017].

  9. ^

    Haidt, J. (2001) “The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment”, Psychological Review, 108, pp. 814-834.

  10. ^

    Slovic, P.; Zionts, D.; Woods, A.K.; Goodman, R. & Jinks, D. (2013) “Psychic numbing and mass atrocity”, in Shafir, E. (ed.) The behavioral foundations of public policy, Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 126-142.

  11. ^

    Tomasik, B. (2015) “The importance of wild-animal suffering”, Relations: Beyond Anthropocentrism, 3, pp. 133-152 [accessed on 20 May 2017].

Comments6
Sorted by Click to highlight new comments since:

The represented research asks different groups of people how much they would donate to different amounts of birds. Does anyone know if there is also research asking the same group of people how much they want to donate to saving different amounts of animals/humans/future beings? My hypothesis is that even when you ask this to the same group, you do not get a 10x or 100x donation.

Thank you! I found it helpful to put words on these intangible biases. I wonder how AI could help in the future, in that field of decision making and resource allocation. In a way that removes our human biases both on scales of the issues and perceived importance.

Eliezer's Scope Insensitivity is about half the length (3 mins vs 7 mins) and explains the concept just as well if not better. Additionally, the language in this post isn't as clear making it less pleasant to read.

Just as a point of information, the links in the footnotes do not lead to the sources itself but rather to animal-ethics.org.

For me personally, when hovering over the footnote I was confused to always find the same source for all information - just in case you would be open to change the footnotes to the source itself.

Thank you for flagging this! I have just updated the footnotes.

In my opinion it seems to make sense that different animals have different levels of consciousness… maybe given by the fact that humans consciousness has evolved….? Probably? So there are different levels of suffering. Insects are probably next to not conscious at first glance thats what it seems like to me.

Curated and popular this week
Relevant opportunities