29 economists and philosophers, including leading researchers published today in Utilitas: “avoiding the Repugnant Conclusion is not a necessary condition for a minimally adequate... approach to population ethics.” The link at the top of this post is to my own summary of the article and how we reached it, posted at Medium.
Population ethics asks how to evaluate policies and social trends that change the size of the global population. For decades, research has focused on whether to accept “the Repugnant Conclusion.” The Repugnant Conclusion is a hypothetical claim about how to compare populations of well-off people against imaginable, enormous populations of worse-off people. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy explains the Repugnant Conclusion and calls it “one of the cardinal challenges of modern ethics”. In a new publication in the journal Utilitas (link to open access paper), 29 philosophers, economists, and demographers agree: “avoiding the Repugnant Conclusion should no longer be the central goal driving population ethics research.”
The collaborators come from different institutes, continents, and academic disciplines. They also come from different perspectives. Their statement emphasizes that they came to their agreement for different reasons. Some think the Repugnant Conclusion is true. Others are unsure, but think it would be no big deal if true, or just one among many factors to consider. Others coauthors argue that the Repugnant Conclusion makes no sense to begin with.
Population ethics “is not simply an academic exercise, and we should not let it be governed by undue attention to one consideration.”
The collaborators conclude with a hope that population ethics will one day make progress beyond the debates and questions of today: “Perhaps someday the correct approach to axiology, social welfare, or population ethics will be agreed upon among experts. If so, we do not know whether the approach used will entail the Repugnant Conclusion. We should keep our minds open.”
Contact: Dean Spears. dspears@utexas.edu
Citation: Zuber, et al. (2021) Utilitas (link)
I have some sympathy to your general point. However, I think this case is relevantly different from utilitarian philosophers stating they agree with utilitarianism, for the following reasons:
None of these claims have true analogs for utilitarianism. It's not the case that the field of normative ethics was conceived as a project to defeat utilitarianism; there is plenty of work arguing for utilitarianism; etc.
More broadly, I think analytic philosophy has a tendency to spawn 'industries' that produce ever more refined attempts and rebuttals of formal theories that try to provide a solution to some problem, the framing of which is usually taking for granted. Perhaps the most infamous examples are countless attempts to find some definition or 'analysis' of the concept of knowledge in terms of more primitive concepts such as justification, truth, and belief, in response to Edmund Gettier's examples allegedly showing that knowledge can't simply be justified true belief. (Indeed, philosophers have discussed the 'Gettier Problem problem', i.e. the philosophical problem of explaining why solving the original Gettier Problem is pointless or otherwise problematic.) Other examples might be the logical positivist project to reduce meaning to predictions of sense data, attempts at defusing van Inwagen's Consequence Argument for the incompatibility of free will and determinism by providing counterexamples to one of its premises, or the ever-growing zoo of Frankfurt-style examples aimed at showing that moral responsibility does not require a 'could have done otherwise' property.
To the extent that there is progress in philosophy, I think it often consists in disrupting such industries by reframing the problem they were built on or forcefully arguing against some desideratum that was thought to be necessary for a 'solution'. (A more cynical view would be that such work merely replaces one flawed industry with the next.) At the very least, such work has often become famous, e.g. Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, Strawson's Freedom and Resentment, Frankfurt's Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility and Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person, Kripke's Naming and Necessity, etc.
However, a comparison with such contributions also brings me back to where I agree with you: I think these philosophers provided value because they didn't merely state that they disagreed with, or disliked something about some 'industry'. And, crucially, they even went beyond arguing for or explaining their view. They also made a positive contribution by showing how different and more fruitful work could look like. So e.g., roughly speaking, Quine said "you can't 'reduce' the meaning of an individual proposition to anything, you need to look at the full web of beliefs", Strawson said "the basis for moral responsibility lies not in questions whether or not anyone could have done anything otherwise but in people's 'reactive attitudes' toward each others' behavior", Frankfurt regarding the same issue instead pointed to the internal structure of a moral agent's preferences, etc. Then other philosophers can and did make positive contributions by describing how meaning is a holistic property, what it is about the structure of an agent's internal preferences that makes them morally responsible for their actions, etc.
At least at first glance I couldn't find such a positive contribution in the paper we're discussing here. It's all well and good to say that one doesn't like the existing population ethics 'industry' - and I agree, in my view the field has been stale for a long time and has consisted mostly of footnotes to Parfit -, but then what else do you want people to do? Quine wouldn't have been nearly as influential had he said "perhaps one day the correct approach to meaning will be uncovered, but I don't know whether Carnap would agree with it". And I suspect the lack of a clear positive recommendation or other 'way out' may prevent this paper from having the effect it tries to have. Though perhaps only time will tell. (E.g. arguably semantic holism wasn't exactly well developed in Two Dogmas itself.)
--
[1] At least Parfit clearly rejected the Repugnant Conclusion in Reasons and Persons, Part IV of which seems close to a 'founding document' for population ethics. As the authors of the paper discussed here mention, Parfit seems to later have somewhat changed his stance, though my memory from one of his last papers was still that he was hoping to advance some view avoiding the Repugnant Conclusion (through some combination of lexicality and incomparability or vagueness - indeed the paper was titled Can We Avoid the Repugnant Conclusion?). However, I'm no expert on Parfit's late work and could easily be wrong; e.g. I don't know what if anything he says on population ethics in On What Matters.
[2] There are papers on what we'd today call population ethics that precede Parfit's work, and Reasons in Persons in particular. However, my impression is that Parfit's work, and Reasons and Persons in particular, have had a domineering influence over subsequent work in what became known as population ethics, at least among analytic philosophers in a broadly consequentialist tradition. Again, I'm no expert on the history of population ethics, and would welcome corrections.