Take the 2025 EA Forum Survey to help inform our strategy and prioritiesTake the survey
Hide table of contents

[EDITED: I have included a brief outline of the main argument]

For some time, I have been writing about wild animal welfare, defending the claim that we have a positive obligation to intervene in nature to eliminate, or mitigate, naturogenic harms.

A common objection I have encountered, both from other academics and the general public, is that this kind of interference goes against wild animal freedom and is, in general, morally wrong. This seems to be, for instance, Sue Donaldson's & Will Kymlicka's view in their influential Zoopolis.

Well, I've written a paper arguing that taking seriously the value of wild animal freedom actually gives us reasons to interfere in nature to help these animals, rather than against doing so. 

If I'm right, that should increase our credence in the view that we have general positive duties of assistance on behalf of wild animals.

Abstract and link below, for those of you who might be interested. Aftwerwards you can also find a brief outline of the main argument.

On expectation, most wild animals have lives of net suffering due to naturogenic causes. Some have claimed that concern for their well-being gives us reasons to intervene in nature on their behalf. Against this, it has been said that many interventions to assist wild animals would be wrong, even if successful, because they would violate their freedom. According to the Freedom-based Approach I defend in this paper, this view is misguided. Concern for wild animal freedom does indeed gives us reasons to secure these animals against control-undermining interferences, but also to intervene in nature in order to enrich their choices.

https://www.tandfonline.com/eprint/RSTNQD7HT2WI8JPAPAIY/full?target=10.1080/21550085.2023.2200728

Outline

Consider a wild animal, W, and a particular choice-situation, C, defined by a set of mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive options, x and y. Now we will say that

       W’s choice is free with respect to C (x, y) to the extent that:

  1. W has the capacity to choose among any of the options, and y, that define C, and
  2. No other agent interferes with that choice in ways that undermine W’s control over it

The main idea is that there are two main ways of increasing W's freedom over C. One is to make her more secure against interferences by other agents that undermine W's control over her choice. Another is to enrich W's choice by adding high-quality options to the choice situation or removing horrendous ones.

W's freedom as an agent is a function of how secure and rich her choice situations are (or, at least, her most important ones).

Wild animals' choice situations are terribly poor. If their freedom is a moral value, that means we have have moral reasons to try and enrich said choice-situations. For instance, through the various ways which have been suggested in the wild animal ethics literature during the past 15 years or so.

Of course, there's the legitimate worry that some enriching interventions might be control-undermining for some animals. As always, there will be trade-offs and we'll need a theory that tells us when these are justified. We will have to make sure all affected animals' interests are taken into account (as we see them given the best evidence available and our most robust theories) .

Motivation

Why this paper?

I'm a classic utilitarian. Still, in a rather Millian way, I think the ideal of freedom is the optimal proxy for institutional design. This is a way to reason how it would apply to wild animals.

In addition, most people are not utilitarians. I think it's valuable to show them how their conclusions should approximate mine, even assuming their own evaluative and normative principles.

If you can't access the article, but would still like to read it, I can send you a copy. Just drop me an email here.

14

0
0

Reactions

0
0

More posts like this

Comments2


Sorted by Click to highlight new comments since:

Eze - thanks for sharing this paper. To maximize engagement here on EA Forum, it might be helpful to give a slightly longer summary of your key arguments? The abstract is a helpful first step, but it doesn't quite give me a sense of the substance of your argument (and I know a lot of EAs might be interested, but don't have the time to read the whole paper). Look forward to hearing more!

Thanks, Geoffrey. I thought the opportunity cost of doing what you suggest was too high. But maybe you're right. I'll try and edit the post accordingly. 

Curated and popular this week
 ·  · 1m read
 · 
This morning I was looking into Switzerland's new animal welfare labelling law. I was going through the list of abuses that are now required to be documented on labels, and one of them made me do a double-take: "Frogs: Leg removal without anaesthesia."  This confused me. Why are we talking about anaesthesia? Shouldn't the frogs be dead before having their legs removed? It turns out the answer is no; standard industry practice is to cut their legs off while they are fully conscious. They remain alive and responsive for up to 15 minutes afterward. As far as I can tell, there are zero welfare regulations in any major producing country. The scientific evidence for frog sentience is robust - they have nociceptors, opioid receptors, demonstrate pain avoidance learning, and show cognitive abilities including spatial mapping and rule-based learning.  It's hard to find data on the scale of this issue, but estimates put the order of magnitude at billions of frogs annually. I could not find any organisations working directly on frog welfare interventions.  Here are the organizations I found that come closest: * Animal Welfare Institute has documented the issue and published reports, but their focus appears more on the ecological impact and population decline rather than welfare reforms * PETA has conducted investigations and released footage, but their approach is typically to advocate for complete elimination of the practice rather than welfare improvements * Pro Wildlife, Defenders of Wildlife focus on conservation and sustainability rather than welfare standards This issue seems tractable. There is scientific research on humane euthanasia methods for amphibians, but this research is primarily for laboratory settings rather than commercial operations. The EU imports the majority of traded frog legs through just a few countries such as Indonesia and Vietnam, creating clear policy leverage points. A major retailer (Carrefour) just stopped selling frog legs after welfar
 ·  · 1m read
 · 
The Open Wing Alliance 2025 cage-free fulfillment report shows that 92% of cage-free egg commitments with deadlines of 2024 or earlier have been fulfilled, up from 89% last year. The report details a regional breakdown of progress around the world.  Thanks to OWA groups and others for continuing to hold companies around the world accountable for their commitments.
 ·  · 4m read
 · 
Note: This post was crossposted from the Open Philanthropy Farm Animal Welfare Research Newsletter by the Forum team, with the author's permission. The author may not see or respond to comments on this post. ---------------------------------------- > Why ending the worst abuses of factory farming is an issue ripe for moral reform I recently joined Dwarkesh Patel’s podcast to discuss factory farming. I hope you’ll give it a listen — and consider supporting his fundraiser for FarmKind’s Impact Fund. (Dwarkesh is matching all donations up to $250K; use the code “dwarkesh”.) We discuss two contradictory views about factory farming that produce the same conclusion: that its end is either inevitable or impossible. Some techno-optimists assume factory farming will vanish in the wake of AGI. Some pessimists see reforming it as a hopeless cause. Both camps arrive at the same conclusion: fatalism. If factory farming is destined to end, or persist, then what’s the point in fighting it? I think both views are wrong. In fact, I think factory farming sits in the ideal position for moral reform. Because its end is neither inevitable nor impossible, it offers a unique opportunity for advocacy to change the trajectory of human moral progress. Not inevitable Dwarkesh raised an objection to working on factory farming that I often hear from techno-optimists who care about the issue: isn’t its end inevitable? Some cite the long arc of moral progress; others the promise of vast technological change like cultivated meat or Artificial General Intelligence (AGI) which surpasses human capabilities. It’s true that humanity has achieved incredible moral progress for humans. But that progress was never inevitable — it was the result of moral and political reform as much as technology. And that moral progress mostly hasn’t yet extended to animals. For them, the long moral arc of history has so far only bent downward. Technology may one day end factory farming, just as cars liberated w