Note: this post is a (minorly) edited version of a new 80,000 Hours problem profile.
Summary
History is littered with moral mistakes — things that once were common, but we now consider clearly morally wrong, for example: human sacrifice, gladiatorial combat, public executions, witch hunts, and slavery.
In my opinion, there’s one clear candidate for the biggest moral mistake that humanity is currently making: factory farming.
The rough argument is:
- There are trillions of farmed animals, making the scale of the potential problem so large that it’s hard to intuitively grasp.
- The vast majority (we estimate 97.5%)[1] of farmed animals are in factory farms. The conditions in these farms are far worse than most people realise.
- Even if nonhuman animals don’t morally matter as much as humans, there’s good evidence that they are conscious and that they feel pain — and, as a result, the poor conditions in factory farms are likely causing animals to experience severe suffering.
What’s more, we think that this problem is highly neglected and that there are clear ways to make progress — which makes factory farming a highly pressing problem overall.
Scale
We kill around 1.6 to 4.5 trillion animals a year. There’s no consensus about how to compare this to the scale of issues that affect humans, because people disagree about the moral significance of animals. However, we believe there are good reasons to think that the suffering of animals on farms has moral significance. And, just thinking about the suffering involved in the slaughter process, when we adjust for the best quantitative assessment we can find for how 1.6 to 4.5 trillion animals being killed per year compares to human suffering, this amounts to the equivalent of around 60 million to 800 billion humans going through that same experience. (Though this is a very under-researched question, so this conversion should be treated as extremely uncertain – see below.)
This is also just a rough proxy for the scale of the issue; before slaughter, these animals are almost always kept in factory farming conditions, where we’d guess they suffer great harms. As for the future, we expect this problem to worsen in the short term but we would guess that working on it doesn’t have a substantial impact on the very long-term future.
Neglectedness
This issue is highly neglected. We’d estimate there are approximately 3,000 people working on reducing harms from factory farming and around $400 million dedicated to this issue.
Solvability
This seems moderately tractable and there are some plausible ways we could make progress.
Introduction
We're going to start by investigating how important we should consider ending factory farming to be — that is, how much good would be done if we solved the entire problem.
We'll look at:
- How many animals are in farms and how we treat these animals
- The extent to which animals deserve our moral consideration, according to various moral theories
- How factory farming is likely to change in the future, as the quantity and quality of life of future factory farmed animals are also part of assessing the importance of the problem
- How we can compare factory farming with existential risks, which are the main category of other problems we consider most pressing
We'll then look at whether there are ways to make progress and how neglected factory farming is before discussing how you can help solve this problem with your career.
How many animals are in farms?
Every year, we kill somewhere between 400 billion and 3 trillion vertebrates (e.g. cows, chickens, fish) — some are killed for sport and some are dissected for experiments, but the vast majority are either slaughtered for food or die in farms before they're old enough to be purposefully slaughtered.[2]
That doesn't mean there are trillions of animals in farms at any given time, as the lifespan of these animals is often less than a year. There are probably around 120–210 billion vertebrates alive in farms at any given time.[3]
If we include invertebrates (e.g. octopuses, insects, crabs, snails, shrimp) — which is more controversial because we have less evidence of their ability to feel pain — it's more like 1.6–4.5 trillion farmed animals killed per year, and around 350–700 billion animals alive in farms at any given time.
It's much harder to estimate how many of these animals are in factory farms. In part, this is because 'factory farming' doesn't have a clear definition. Generally, we'd say something is a factory farm if it has generally poor welfare conditions and a large number of animals in a small space ('high stocking density').
Rather than drawing a clear distinction, we'll go through how different animals tend to be treated on farms and note any key variations, such as in standards between countries[4] or what it means for hens to be 'cage free.'
We don't to focus on animals that aren't farmed — wild animal welfare and animals killed by fishing and hunting are whole separate issues.[5]
This table shows some estimates for various species. For vertebrates, we've only included species where we farm more than 100 million animals at any one time (so, for example, frogs and turtles but not snakes or salamanders). We've included data for all vertebrate species we could find – we farm many other invertebrates, like cephalopods (e.g. squid), and bivalves (e.g. clams, oysters), but we couldn't find any good estimates of how many of these animals are in farms.
Farmed animal | Alive in farms at any one time | Slaughtered per year |
Chickens | 24 billion (10 billion broilers – chickens bred for meat; 7–10 billion egg-laying hens) | 72–77 billion (69 billion for meat; 3-9 billion male chicks from the egg industry) |
Pigs | 1 billion | 1.5 billion |
Cattle (cows) | 1.5 billion | 0.3 billion |
Sheep and goats | 2.2 billion | 1 billion |
Ducks | 1 billion | 3 billion |
Quail | 0.5 billion | 1.5–2.5 billion |
Turkeys | 0.5 billion | 0.7 billion |
Geese and guinea fowls | 0.4 billion | 0.7 billion |
Fish | 100–180 billion | 100 billion |
Frogs | 0.1–2.6 billion | 0.3–1 billion |
Chinese softshell turtles | 0.3–2.1 billion | 0.2–0.9 billion |
Crabs | -- | 5–15 billion |
Crayfish and lobsters | -- | 40–60 billion |
Shrimp | -- | 210–530 billion |
Snails | -- | 3–8 billion |
Crickets | 35–40 billion | 370–430 billion |
Mealworms | 25–30 billion | 290–310 billion |
Black soldier files | 8–16 billion | 190–300 billion |
How do we treat these animals?
Let's go through some of the most commonly farmed animals and look at how they're treated.
In general, the main issues seem to be:
- Poor methods for pre-slaughter stunning, and for slaughter itself
- Extremely crowded and dirty living conditions
- High rates of disease and injury
- Particularly poor conditions during transport
- Occasional withdrawals of food and water for extended periods
- High rates of painful procedures, often carried out without anaesthetic
We think it's important to be sceptical of many of the claims of animal advocates — like anyone advocating for a cause, they have incentives to exaggerate their claims. So we've relied as much as possible on academic, industry, and government sources, and given extensive detail in the footnotes. We tried hard not to cherry-pick the worst cases of animal abuse — this just reflects how the vast majority of animals are treated.
We’ve carefully selected photographs of what we think represent ‘normal’ farms. Photographs of factory farms can be disturbing, so we’ve haven’t included them in this post. Instead, you can find the photographs in the version of this article on our website.
Farmed chickens
We've genetically selected broiler chickens to grow very fast; they may reach the weight for slaughter in as little as five weeks.[6] This fast development causes fluid to build up in the abdomen, which compresses organs, causing pain and breathing difficulties. This build-up of fluid is known as ascites.[7] These chickens' large sizes also cause difficulty moving. Much like injured humans, chickens change the way they move in response to their weight and injury — which then causes muscle and bone pain.[8]
Their movement is also very restricted, and even on free-range farms each bird often has only around 0.1m² of space.[9] Long periods of standing and lying in waste causes painful lesions and chemical burns (specifically, 'hock burn' and 'footpad dermatitis').[10] Heat stress is common due to temperatures of 30 to 40°C in housing.[11]
Diseases are common. One of the most common is necrotic enteritis (a bacterial infection that destroys the small intestine over the course of about 3–4 days).[12] In developing countries, diseases like visceral gout (kidney failure leading to poor appetite and uric acid build up on organs), coccidiosis (a gastrointestinal illness), and colibacillosis (E. coli infection) are common.[13]
Breeder chickens can live for up to a year, but because they're still broiler chickens, they're bred to want to eat a lot. Feeding breeders isn't that helpful for farmers (in fact, it can lead to injury, health issues, and fewer chicks being born), so instead they are kept on the edge of starvation.[14]
Before slaughter, chickens must be 'caught' and loaded into trucks for transport. This process involves humans or a machine picking up and loading chickens into crates. Often, this is done to half the flock, while the rest are left without food or water for days until they are also collected. This process is known as 'depopulation.'[15]
In some systems, like those in Europe, 90% of chickens are stunned before slaughter,[16] mostly by having their heads dunked in water with an electric current. In other countries, like the US, there are no rules governing how chickens are killed.[17] Many chickens experience severe pain when they are shackled upside down by their legs prior to stunning.[18] Chickens then have their throats cut ('bleeding'), before being killed using hot water — as a result, many chickens are boiled alive when the previous steps fail.[19]
Caged laying hens tend to have around 0.07 m² of space, which prevents typical movement and behaviours, including standing, preening, turning, and wing flapping, and prevents them from engaging in natural behaviours like nesting or foraging.[20] Osteoporosis leads to frequent fractures of the keel bone (the part of the sternum where the wings attach).[21] Withdrawal of food and exposure to 24-hour bright lights is sometimes used to induce shedding and regrowth of feathers (known as moulting) to increase egg production in countries outside of Europe.[22] Egg peritonitis — an infection caused by yolks remaining within their body cavity from eggs that break before they are laid — is quite common, causes substantial pain, and is sometimes fatal.[23]
The lives of cage-free hens are marginally better. They are usually kept in indoor aviaries, and free-range hens go outside less than consumers expect.[24] Cage-free hens have a little more space per bird, and are able to move around somewhat. Keel bone fractures are still common.[25]
However, because of stress and the inability to socialise naturally with such a large flock, hens still end up wounding each other by pecking and sometimes even resort to cannibalism.[26] As a result, it's common to remove the tip of both caged and cage-free hens' beaks using a hot blade, without anaesthesia. Beaks are highly sensitive and used by birds to interact with the world, similar to how humans use their hands.[27] Male chicks are killed by maceration.[28] Egg-laying hens are depopulated and slaughtered when they are old enough that their productivity drops, with similar issues to the slaughter or broiler chickens.[29]
Other birds (ducks, quail, turkeys, gueese, guinea fowls) are treated very similarly to chickens).
Farmed pigs
Most farmed pigs are kept indoors on high-density farms.[30] Heat stress is common, reaching temperatures of 30 to 40°C — which is particularly bad as pigs do not sweat; instead they keep cool in the wild through wallowing and rooting.[31]
Piglets go through the removal of parts of their canine teeth (known as tooth cutting)[32] and their tails (known as tail docking)[33] without anaesthesia. Most male piglets are also castrated (other than in the UK and some EU countries) to prevent the strong odour and taste of meat associated with uncastrated pigs (known as 'boar taint').[34]
A small proportion of pigs are kept outdoors. However, these pigs usually have metal or wire rings inserted into their noses (nose ringing), which deliberately causes pain when pigs go to root in order to prevent the ground from being upturned.[35]
The worst conditions are experienced by breeding sows. In countries other than Sweden and the UK, pregnant sows are kept in gestation crates — small pens so narrow that they cannot move or even turn around.[36] And in countries other than Sweden, Norway, and Switzerland, farrowing crates are used after birth to prevent sows being able to move away from their piglets.[37] Piglets are weaned at around 3–4 weeks, after which sows are inseminated again immediately, leaving them little time outside of these small pens.[38]
At slaughter, pigs undergo electric stunning, controlled atmosphere stunning (gassing with carbon dioxide), or are not stunned for shackling (i.e. live-shackle slaughter), after which the major arteries near the heart are severed.[39]
Farmed cattle
Generally, cattle are treated better than chickens and pigs, with 5–10 m² of space per cattle.[40]
The main issues are:
- Many dairy cows are kept in cubicle housing or tie-in stalls (where they are tethered to the stall by their neck) with limited access to pasture for half of the year.[41] Beef cattle are often 'feedlot-finished,' meaning they are kept indoors for 100 to 600 days to increase weight gain.[42]
- Calves have their early horns (known as "'buds'") removed by having their heads burned with a hot iron, or through chemical burns, often without anaesthesia. Older cattle sometimes go through a much more painful process where their grown horns are removed using tools like shears or saws.[43]
- Lameness (damage or weakness to limbs) and mastitis (inflammation of the udder) are common causes of pain in dairy cows.[44] Indoor floors for beef cattle usually have gaps in them to allow excrement to fall through, but this makes injury much more common.[45]
- Dairy cows are kept pregnant to ensure constant milk production. This creates an issue: dealing with the unwanted calves. All male calves and almost all female calves are separated from their mothers pretty much immediately — both calves and mothers appear to cry for each other for days to weeks afterwards.[46]
- Male calves from the dairy industry are often killed shortly after they're born.[47] This is because dairy cows and meat cows are different breeds bred for different traits. If they are kept for meat, it's usually veal. Veal calves are fed an iron-restricted diet to keep their flesh pale. Outside the EU, veal calves are usually raised in single-occupancy crates no bigger than the calves: these prevent almost all socialisation and movement for some or all of their (short) lives.[48]
- Transportation to the slaughterhouse is stressful, with cattle spending long periods in cramped conditions without food or water. Dairy cows that are no longer producing milk at a profitable rate usually have some kind of injury or disease, making it harder to deal with these sorts of conditions.[49]
- At slaughter, the use of electric goads causes pain, and there are poor conditions in the resting areas at slaughterhouses. Cattle are usually stunned with a bolt gun or electric shock, which often fails, leaving cattle conscious when they are hung upside down by one leg while their throats are cut and their trachea removed. Throat-cutting sometimes intentionally occurs without stunning.[50]
Farmed sheep and goats
Sheep and goats also tend to be treated better than chickens and pigs, and are largely kept in extensive farms.
The main issues are:
- Both sheep and goats are castrated. The usual method is by tying an elastic ring around the scrotum, restricting blood flow while the scrotum gradually dies and then falls off. In sheep, the same is also done to their tails, which take 4–6 weeks to fall off. This is often done without anaesthesia.[51]
- Goats have their early horns (known as 'buds') removed by having their heads burned with a hot iron, often without anaesthesia.[52]
- Lameness (damage or weakness to limbs) is a common cause of pain. In sheep, this is often caused by bacterial infections known as foot rot and foot scald.[53]
- Mastitis (inflammation of the udder) is relatively rare in sheep and goats kept for milk production, but can be very painful.[54]
- Around 15–20% of lambs die on farms before slaughter — for example, from disease, extreme hot or cold temperatures, or starvation. Around half of these die soon after birth, often because of complications resulting from the birth itself.[55]
- Lambs are separated from their mothers well before they would naturally leave, which has a clear behavioural (and likely emotional) effect on both lambs and their mothers.[56]
- Transport to slaughter is often in overcrowded trucks without food or water. When trucks are stationary in hot weather, sheep and goats experience extreme heat.[57]
- While waiting for slaughter, sheep and goats are in cramped conditions with limited access to food and water. They are stunned with a blow to the head or by electrocuting their heads, although not all sheep and goats are stunned successfully — and some are not stunned at all.[58]
Farmed fish
We're more uncertain about what produces a poor welfare environment for fish, and there are so many different species of fish that it's difficult to say much about their welfare in general. For example, it seems like some fish prefer high stocking density environments. (There are a variety of reasons for this, including that high stocking density can prevent territorial and aggressive behaviour).[59] Other fish species seem to prefer more turbid (murky, dirty-looking) water to clean water.[60]
That said, there are almost no legal protections for fish welfare.[61] Somewhere between 15 billion and one trillion fish die in farms before reaching slaughter age,[62] and that high pre-slaughter mortality rate is a bad sign for their general welfare.
Common issues in fish farms include:
- Poor water quality, including insufficient dissolved oxygen; inappropriate temperature, pH, and salinity; and build ups of ammonia and nitrates from waste[63]
- Disease and parasites,[64] such as sea lice[65]
- Other stressors related to the harsh environment — like withdrawal of feed — which lead to injury (e.g. fin erosion),[66] and cannibalism[67]
Since fish are smaller than most land-based farm animals, more fish are killed for the same amount of food. What's more, unlike herbivorous land-based farm animals, predatory fish such as tuna and salmon (and the lesser-known mandarin fish)[68] must be fed other fish, which are often still alive, increasing the welfare concerns per animal sold.
Many issues occur at slaughter. Common slaughter methods include:[69]
- Leaving fish in air to slowly suffocate to death over the course of several minutes[70]
- Putting fish in baths of ice slurry where they gradually lose consciousnes. In theory, fish are left until they die from lack of oxygen before they're cut open and drained of blood. But sometimes, if fish aren't left in the ice slurry long enough, or if there isn't the right ratio of ice to water and fish, they can recover and regain brain function as they warm up, leaving them conscious when they're cut open.[71]
- Bubbling carbon dioxide into the fish's water to make it gradually acidic, which eventually stuns the. Fish will swim vigorously and try to escape the tank when this is done. Again, if fish are removed too early or the water doesn't become acidic enough, they'll be conscious when they are cut open.[72]
- Simply cutting off the gills of a fish, causing them to bleed out and suffocate to death[73]
Farmed frogs and turtles
Frogs and turtles are kept at such high density that they must stand on top of each other to have enough space. Tadpoles and froglets have extremely high rates of disease — in particular, septicemia, which can frequently cause swelling of the whole body and for the stomach to hang out of the frog's mouth, as well as convulsions, paralysis, and death. Farmed Chinese softshell turtles have high rates of white-spot disease, which causes skin lesions, lack of eating, and eventually death.[74]
Frogs are stunned by being left in an ice bath for around 15 minutes or by being given a few-second-long electric shock, after which they are cut open — but we're unsure about compliance or success rates. We're unsure how Chinese softshell turtles are slaughtered, but it's claimed that turtles are often beheaded or have their shells removed without stunning.[75]
Farmed shrimp and crustaceans
The main welfare issues for shrimp (the vast majority of farmed decapod crustaceans) are:[76]
- Poor water quality — which could include a lack of oxygen to breathe, or swimming around in their own waste
- Disease — symptoms include spots, lethargy, body deformities, changes in colour, reduced food intake, and death
- Eyestalk ablation — blinding shrimp by removing one or both of their eyestalks, usually by pinching, cutting, or burning them off
- Slaughter — by being left in the air to suffocate or being crushed by other shrimp
Crustaceans more broadly are routinely boiled alive just before being eaten — and therefore travel extremely long distances while alive.
Other farmed invertebrates (snails and insects)
We're very uncertain about what produces a poor welfare environment for these animals.
Welfare concerns for snails appear to include: high stocking densities, disease, purging (starvation before transport to ensure there's no undigested food left inside when they're eaten), live transport, and slaughter by boiling alive.[77]
The main welfare concerns for insects (including black soldier flies, mealworms, and crickets) include: high stocking densities,[78] disease and parasites,[79] cannibalism,[80] injury,[81] handling stress (such as vibrations that may be perceived as predatory attack, or exposing light-averse insects to bright lights),[82] withdrawal of food before slaughter or from adults (in particular, black soldier fly adults are never fed),[83] live transport,[84] and slaughter by roasting, baking, microwaving, freezing in air or asphyxiation — all without anaesthesia.[85]
To what extent do animals deserve our moral consideration?
On reading the above, it's pretty clear that if even some animals deserve our moral consideration, something pretty awful is happening. But to what extent some or all animals deserve our moral consideration is, in fact, a subject of substantial debate.
We're going to look at:
- Whether animals are conscious and whether they feel pain
- What various ethical theories say about which beings deserve our moral consideration — we'll consider a wellbeing-based approach, as well as other moral theories
- Some quantitative estimates, based on these discussions, of how many animals it'd be reasonable to count morally the equivalent to one human, to help estimate the scale of the moral problem of factory farming
Overall, we find that while there's disagreement on these issues, and grappling with this moral uncertainty is tricky, there's generally enough agreement on the science and among plausible moral theories that the correct approach is to give many species of nonhuman animals — including the ones we keep on factory farms — at least some non-negligible moral consideration.
Animal consciousness and pain
Many of the moral arguments we'll consider below come down to whether animals are conscious and whether they have the capacity to feel pain.
The question of consciousness remains highly philosophical. By consciousness, we mean phenomenal consciousness (or capable of subjective experience) — that is, we mean that there is 'something it's like' to be a certain animal in the same way there's 'something it's like' for you to experience a sunset or a good mood.
The main ways we get evidence about the consciousness of other humans is by communicating via language and by analogy to our own minds (if you're conscious, other people probably are too). But we can't clearly communicate with nonhuman animals, and their minds are less similar to our own, so it's harder to argue by analogy.
But there is plausibly a way to make progress. By looking at the various philosophical and scientific theories of consciousness, we can try to identify "potentially conscious-indicating features,"[86] and then look for these features in animals.
A 2017 report by researcher Luke Muehlhauser identified over 40 features which are indicative of consciousness.[87] They fall into a few categories:
- Broad similarity with humans — there are, of course, many ways to measure this. Following Muehlhauser, we'll look at the time since the closest common ancestor with humans.[88] The other three categories in this list can also be seen as measures of similarity with humans.
- Neurobiological features — in particular, having a large brain and a centralised, complex nervous system.
- Clear and complex nociception — the physical states and behaviours associated with feeling pain in humans. For example, having fibres that respond to dangerous stimuli (known as "nociceptors"), protective behaviour like wound guarding or limping, responding to painkillers, and learning to avoid things that cause nociceptors to fire.
- Other indicators of cognitive ability — like play behaviour,[89] grief behaviour, mirror self-recognition, tool use, language capabilities, or theory of mind. While the relationship between cognitive ability and phenomenal consciousness is not well understood, many philosophers and scientists think there's likely an association between the two.[90]
So let's look at some of the animals we keep in factory farms and assess them on some of these criteria.
We'll pay particular attention to nociception, because it's both an indicator of consciousness, and also — as we'll see below — plausibly an indication of these creatures being worthy of moral concern in themselves (that is, that they have 'moral status').[91]
Unfortunately, there's still a lot we don't know in this area (even things like how many neurons are in the brains of various animals). So there are lots of gaps in the tables below — even among the small number of indicators we've decided to focus on.
Humans | Chickens | Pigs | Fish | Insects | |
Time since closest ancestor with humans[88] | N/A | 310 million years ago | 95 million years ago | 400 million years ago (lungfish) to 530 million years ago (jawless fish) | 700 million years ago |
Brain and nervous system | Avg. adult brain mass: 1300g[92] Neurons in brain: 85 billion[93] Have a neocortex and a central nervous system | Avg. adult brain mass: 3.5g[94] Neurons in brain: 220 million[95] May have a neocortex-like structure[96] and have a central nervous system | Avg. adult brain mass: 135g[97] Neurons in the brain: 430 million[98] Have a neocortex[99] and a central nervous system | Avg. adult brain mass: 0.2g (rainbow trout), 0.3g (carp), 1g (salmon)[100] Total number of neurons: 10 million (zebrafish)[101] Don’t have a neocortex,[102] but do have a central nervous system | Avg. adult brain mass: 3mg (bees), 1.6mg (*Apoidea*), 0.6mg (black soldier flies), 0.4 to 0.06mg (butterflies)[103] Total number of neurons: 600,000 (western honey bee), 300,000 (black soldier fly), 100,000 (fruit fly)[104] Have a central nervous system but nothing clearly resembling a neocortex |
Nociception[105] | Neural nociceptors and reflexes to move away from dangerous stimuli Nociceptors respond to painkillers Self-administer painkillers if needed (and even pay a cost to do so) Exhibit protective behaviour (e.g. wound guarding, limping) | Neural nociceptors[106] and reflexes to move away from dangerous stimuli[107] Nociceptors respond to painkillers Self-administer painkillers if needed (no studies were found on whether they would pay a cost to do so).[108] Exhibit protective behaviour[109] | Have neural nociceptors[110] and reflexes to move away from dangerous stimuli[111] Nociceptors respond to painkillers,[112] but no studies were found on self-administration Exhibit protective behaviour.[113] | Have neural nociceptors and reflexes to move away from dangerous stimuli[114] Nociceptors respond to painkillers. They may self-administer painkillers if needed (and pay a cost to do so), but the evidence is unclear (zebrafish)[115] Exhibit protective behaviour (carp, zebrafish, rainbow trout)[116] | Have neural nociceptors, and reflexes to move away from dangerous stimuli Nociceptors respond to painkillers[117] Exhibit protective behaviour (bumblebees)[118] |
Other indicators of cognitive ability[105] | Play behaviours and grief behaviours Clear tool use Recognise themselves in mirrors[119] Can move around obstacles to reach a goal (even when they temporarily can’t sense the goal)[120] A range of other cognitive abilities not observed in other animals which people have argued indicate consciousness, such as abstract language capabilities and the ability to do mental time travel | Play behaviours[121] Grief behaviours have been claimed by some backyard chicken owners,[122] but we found no studies confirming this No clear tool use[123] Might recognise themselves in mirrors (although don’t pass the conventional mirror test)[124] Can move around obstacles to reach a goal (even when they temporarily can’t sense the goal)[125] | Play behaviours,[126] and likely experience grief (but we’re not sure)[127] Tool use[128] Do not pass the mirror test[129] Can move around obstacles to reach a goal (even when they temporarily can’t sense the goal)[130] | Likely play behaviours,[131] but no clear grief behaviours Tool use (wrasse, cichlids, whitetail majors)[132] Cleaner wrasse pass the mirror test[133] Can move around obstacles to reach a goal (even when they temporarily can’t sense the goal) (zebrafish, goldfish)[134] | Most indicators have not been studied Some complex behaviours have been found, including: |
Each indicator that's present for a species is some evidence for its consciousness; similarly, each indicator that's missing is some evidence against.
But it's not really clear how much evidence each indicator provides — without a decisive underlying theory, there's no obvious way to interpret the data. And this table is notably incomplete, so much so that evidence not included is probably more significant than the evidence presented!
We know of two other surveys of the evidence that look at many more possible indicators and a wider variety of species,[140] but these are also still very incomplete.
There are other issues with these indicators:[141]
- Many systems typically thought to be non-conscious (for example the spinal cord, plants, bacteria, and some computer programs) have at least some of the above features.
- Many of the behaviours discussed can also occur unconsciously in humans, which suggests they're not great evidence for consciousness.[142]
- And lots of the information might be mistaken — much of this is based on single studies, many of which may fail to replicate.
That said, if you're anything like me, you probably find the extent to which animals express complex behaviours pretty surprising — which suggests that we should be more confident they are conscious. In fact, it seems like we are generally finding, over time, that sophisticated behaviours are more common than we once thought.
There may be other ways of making progress on whether animals are conscious, but we haven't found any to be particularly illuminating.[143]
Overall, there are three takeaways we feel pretty confident in:
- It seems very hard to rule out that the animals we keep on farms are conscious.
- It seems even harder to rule out the existence of nociception in these species.
- The evidence varies from species to species, and seems stronger for animals like pigs and chickens than for fish or insects.
It seems to us that, given the evidence we currently have and the huge uncertainty, it's hard to justify thinking that the probability of consciousness for any factory farmed animal is less than, say, 5%. And for some animals (chickens, sheep, goats, cows, pigs), I think the chances of consciousness seem above 80%.
What makes something deserving of moral consideration?
So, if some species of animals are conscious and have nociceptors (pain responses) or emotion, what does that imply about their moral status?
We've argued previously that a core aspect of doing good is about promoting wellbeing, considered impartially. In short, this is because when it comes down to it, most moral theories agree that:
- If you can make others better off — i.e. increase wellbeing — that's a good thing to do.
- It's even better to make more individuals better off than fewer.
- This is true equally, no matter who those individuals are (as long as, and to the extent that, they are capable of wellbeing).
(Read about this argument in more detail.)
So we can then consider whether each species has something that constitutes 'wellbeing.'
There are three broad theories of wellbeing:
- The hedonistic view, where what matters is the degree of positive vs negative experienced mental states (e.g. happiness vs pain)
- The preference satisfaction view, where wellbeing means getting what you (perhaps most deeply) want
- Objective list theories, where wellbeing consists of achieving things on a 'list' of objectively good states or events, e.g. friendship, knowledge, happiness, love, virtue, wisdom, and health
Overall, the hedonistic view appears to place the most confidence in animals having the capacity for wellbeing — it seems clear that if an animal is conscious and has pain responses or emotion, then they can have positive or negative experiences.
It's less obvious that animals have preferences — nailing down exactly what philosophers mean by preferences is really difficult — but that many animals act to avoid pain is at least suggestive of the concept of preferences. (That said, some preference utilitarians argue that preferences require language, e.g. R. G. Frey.)
It's also very unclear to what extent animals have the capacity for virtue or wisdom — so animals might be missing the capacity for many important items on objective list theories of wellbeing. But in practice, most people (including philosophers of wellbeing) would include 'lack of pain' and 'happiness or pleasure' as important goods to obtain on any 'objective list.'
This suggests that on every mainstream view, there's an argument that animals are capable of wellbeing, though it's especially clear in the hedonistic case.
There's lots more to discuss here, and many more objections and counter-objections to consider. For a more in-depth discussion, we'd recommend Comparisons of Capacity for Welfare and Moral Status Across Species by Jason Shukraft.
Different moral approaches
Many people believe some version of 'welfarism' — the view that the welfare of individuals is in fact the only source of moral value.
If welfarism is right, the above analysis suggests that animals do deserve our moral consideration, since they seem likely to be conscious and to be capable of welfare and suffering.
There are good arguments for welfarism, but we think it makes sense not to be too confident in any particular moral theory — so it's worth considering what other views have to say about the moral standing of animals.
Do any other popular theories suggest that, even if factory farming is large in scale, solvable and neglected, we should nevertheless not consider it to be a particularly pressing problem because animals shouldn't be given much (or any) moral consideration?
There is too much here to give a comprehensive overview, but here are short descriptions of some of the most well-known theories and what they have to say about animals:
- Kantian personhood. Kant argues that fundamental moral value comes from being a rational being — and that only humans meet his criteria for being rational. In recent years, philosopher Christine Korsgaard has developed this idea into the claim that humans face a unique "problem of normativity" as a result of our ability to think about our desires. One common critique of this approach is the problem of "marginal cases": many humans, like babies and people in comas, don't have the capacity for rationality or self-reflection in the sense required by Kant and Korsgaard, but do seem to deserve moral consideration. Korsgaard rejects this critique, but nevertheless concludes that animals should be treated as "ends in themselves" under a Kantian view of ethics. (Read more on Kantian personhood.)
- Contractarianism similarly only grants moral status to rational agents that can comprehend the idea of a social contract. Mark Rowlands argues that some forms of contractarianism do grant status to animals, because behind a veil of ignorance (where the moral choice is the one you would make if you didn't know your ethnicity, gender, social status, or species), one would support the moral consideration of animals. That said, it's common to interpret contractarianism as excluding animals from moral concern because in a thought experiment of forming a social contract, they're not sophisticated enough to participate. However, one prominent defender of a related view, T. M. Scanlon, notes that his version of contractualism only accounts for one domain of morality (what we owe to other people) — which doesn't rule out that other domains (such as obligations with regard to the environment) could include moral reasons to respect the interests of animals.
- Rights-based approaches. Many philosophers have argued for and against the concept of animal rights. Tom Regan argues that all mammals of at least one year in age have rights, because they have certain cognitive abilities like perception, memory, sense of the future, and capacity for pain. Gary Francione argues that animals have the right not to be owned, and that just that one right is sufficient for a huge change to our practices. Carl Cohen – a critic of rights-based approaches to animal rights — argues that rights-holders must have the capacity to comprehend 'rules of duty'. It's also common to think that rights are an important part of morality and that protecting the welfare of individuals is good too, even if it's separate, or less important. So a rights-based approach seems to not lean clearly one way or another.
- Capabilities approach. This approach, developed by Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen, suggests that a just society arises if people are given the chance to flourish and achieve things like health, safety, and social relationships. Nussbaum argues that this approach requires us to also let animals achieve, at the very least, a lack of suffering. (Read more in her book, Justice for Animals.)
- Virtue ethics. Virtue ethics approaches tend to think that compassion and care, including for animals, are virtues, but disagree on the extent to which this implies actions like refraining from factory farming.
- Even if animals have moral standing, there are views of what it means for some state of the world to be better than another that might suggest that factory farming isn't such a pressing concern — in particular, person-affecting views. These views argue that we only have moral obligations to help those who are already alive, not to enable more people or other beings to exist with good lives. Since the vast majority of animals on farms live very short lives (usually less than a year), most of the problem of factory farming arises with regard to the treatment of animals who aren't yet born. As a result, even if we do give moral consideration to animals, the scale of the problem is substantially reduced under these person affecting views, which would make it much less pressing overall. That said, philosophers who defend person affecting views often think there's an asymmetry where, while it's not good to bring someone with a good life into existence, it is bad to bring someone into existence just to suffer. If that's right, the problem of factory likely remains very large. (Read more about person-affecting views).
- Finally, many "common sense" approaches to ethics suggest that many of the standard industry practices in factory farming (described above) are wrong, even if they don't have a considered view about animals' moral standing.
So it's not the case that no matter what your view of morality, factory farming is an especially pressing issue. However, most moral theories seem to put at least some weight on animals (often as a result of their consciousness and capacity to feel pain, and sometimes as a result of apparent preferences or capacity for flourishing). Since we're philosophically uncertain about the nature of morality or the moral standing of animals, we don't think we can rule out the basic argument above that animals do have moral standing, making factory farming a large-scale problem.
You also don't need to treat every moral theory as having a vote in your deliberation — an alternative approach to moral uncertainty is to think about how confident you are in a given moral theory and think about the expected choiceworthiness of an action.
For us, both approaches point to giving at least some non-negligible moral weight to animals, and plausibly quite a lot — though your views could be sufficiently different that you disagree.
How many animals count morally the same as one human?
Even if animals deserve our moral consideration, it doesn't mean that we should count animals the same way we count humans.
Counting the number of individuals
Counting the number of people affected is usually important for how we compare the effects of actions that only affect humans — an action that affects two humans is considered twice as important as one that affects only one human (all else equal).
If moral status doesn't have degrees (i.e. something is either worthy of moral consideration or not), a view argued for by philosophers such as Kant, Regan, and Francione, then this sounds like a reasonable way to count animals too, as long as the animals meet the criteria for moral consideration.
However, this leads to some strange conclusions, like an overriding consideration for the welfare of insects because they are so numerous.
It also seems plausible that moral status does come in degrees — in which case we should ask how much moral status each animal has.
Counting the number of neurons
One common way trying to approximate the moral status of different animals is assuming each individual has some fixed capacity for wellbeing in fixed proportion to the number of neurons they have.[144]
This substantially changes how we compare animals to humans.[145]
Total population | Neurons per animal | Total neurons across the population | |
---|---|---|---|
Humans | 8 billion | 85 billion | 700 quintillion |
Chickens | 24 billion | 220 million | 5 quintillion |
Pigs | 1 billion | 430 million | 0.5 quintillion |
Cows | 1.5 billion | 6 billion | 9 quintillion |
Farmed fish | 100 billion to 180 billion | 10 million | 1 to 2 quintillion |
While this method is simple, and tempting, we think there are lots of good objections to using solely neuron counts as proxies to moral weight. These objections focus on showing that while neuron count probably does correlate with the amount of moral consideration you should give an animal, these correlations are very imperfect. For example, there are a large number of studies showing that decreased brain volume can increase the intensity of experiences (like chronic pain) in humans.[146]
As a result, we think we can't conclude much just from neuron counts, other than that we should probably give somewhat more consideration to humans than to nonhuman animals. The extent of that additional moral consideration remains unclear — and neuron counts seem a poor proxy.
Trying to estimate the probability of consciousness
Rather than just using neuron counts, we can attempt to come up with an estimate of how likely we think each species is to be conscious — and then weigh each individual by that probability.
Ultimately, this is very difficult to do, and we haven't found any work that does much better than the conclusion we already came to above: that it's hard to justify thinking that the probability of consciousness for any adult factory farmed animal is less than around 5 percent.[147]
Using welfare ranges
The most recent and most comprehensive approach to comparing animals to humans was pioneered by Jason Schukraft and Bob Fischer, two philosophers working for Rethink Priorities' Moral Weight Project.
They try to assess animals' capacity for welfare, which they split into two components:
- Their lifespan — if animals live longer, they will experience more
- Their welfare range — how much capacity they have for welfare in each moment
To assess these welfare ranges, Rethink Priorities got together a team of three philosophers, two comparative psychologists, two fish welfare researchers, two entomologists, an animal welfare scientist, and a veterinarian. They listed 82 different possible proxies for welfare ranges (things like animals' response to painkillers, the mirror test, or finding depression-like behaviour), and investigated them for a range of animals.
Next, they aggregated this information using 12 different assumptions, for example:[148]
- Going by neuron count alone
- Using multiple different quantitative measures (such as brain mass to body mass ratio and the maximum number of nociceptor spikes per second), and then taking a weighted average of the ratio between these values and the values in humans
- Looking at the proportion of the qualitative proxies each animal has compared to humans (humans have all the proxies)
- Looking at just certain subsets of the proxies or using quantitative adjustments that exaggerate the differences between species
Using nine of these assumptions (mainly qualitative assumptions as well as neuron counts), the researchers used a simulation to determine welfare scores, and quantified their uncertainty.[149]
They then made two adjustments to the models:
- The researchers assumed there is a 28% chance that an animal's subjective experience of time varies by species. That is, perhaps there are more "experienced moments" per second for some species than others, that should increase the welfare range. They tried to estimate this effect.[150]
- The researchers made some guesses about the probability each animal was conscious.
Finally, they combined the results from these nine assumptions.[151] Here are their results:[152]
The means and medians are surprisingly high — based on the mean values, chickens have a welfare range only three times smaller than humans, compared to 1,000 times smaller when using the neuron count method. Even insects, like black soldier flies, have only approximately 100 times smaller ranges than humans. (Rethink Priorities have argued that this result shouldn't be surprising.)
That said, the main thing to take away from this graph is the high uncertainty: the error bars (representing a 90% confidence interval) are huge.[153] There's also a lot that's subjective here. For example, the researchers estimated an approximately 40% chance that salmon are conscious. If you adjusted this to the 5% lower bound on consciousness for adult farmed animals we suggested above, you'd get an almost 10 times lower estimate (note silkworms are juveniles).
There are also some ways in which these could be underestimates of welfare ranges. In particular, the researchers assumed that if they couldn't find any studies on a particular proxy, the species did not have that trait, effectively penalising less-studied animals.
Overall, we think the main thing we think this work shows is that extremely low welfare ranges (below 1%) are unlikely. So we think it makes sense to conclude that adjusting for animals' capacity for welfare likely doesn't change our estimate of the scale of the problem of factory farming as a whole by very much.
Interview: Bob Fischer
Bob Fischer is a senior research manager at Rethink Priorities, an associate professor of philosophy at Texas State University, and the director of the Society for the Study of Ethics and Animals. He discussed his work on Rethink Priorities' Moral Weight Project on our podcast.
How might factory farming change in the future?
Here's a graph of the number of land animals being slaughtered each year:
The number of animals being slaughtered is increasing. This is also true for fish farming:
It seems likely that trends will be similar for shellfish and other invertebrates (there's a nascent and growing insect farming industry).[154]
Ultimately, we'd guess this trend is primarily caused by the human population getting bigger and richer, increasing the demand for meat.
The number of animals on factory farms isn't increasing as much in developed countries. This is probably primarily because their populations aren't growing as much. It also seems that as income per capita increases, meat consumption per capita also increases — but possibly only up to a point. In a few countries, meat consumption per capita is now falling.[155] We're not quite sure why this is, but we'd guess that, in part, as people get rich enough, they start being more willing to do things like change their diets in response to climate, health, or animal welfare concerns.
But overall, it looks like meat consumption — particularly from fish and chickens — is going to continue to substantially increase in the short term.
We think roughly all of this increased demand will be met by factory farming — as opposed to bucolic family farms — since it's by far the cheapest way to produce meat, and probably the only way to produce meat at the scale being demanded without turning most of the planet into grassland.
This could be changed by regulations. Some countries have passed laws to protect the welfare of some farmed animals — but these are far from universal, are poorly enforced, and usually are only small initial steps.
Looking further ahead, meat consumption might stop rapidly increasing if much of the world becomes wealthy enough that average meat consumption per capita stabilises, and the global population stops increasing — which the UN projects will happen around 2080:[156]
But if you're looking that far into the future, all the way to 2080, there are so many things that might change about factory farming by then — not just the number of humans who can buy meat. Society's values might have changed hugely. There might have been a major catastrophe, like a nuclear war or a major pandemic. And perhaps most importantly, technology might completely change the picture.
How will factory farming be affected by technological advances?
We asked some experts what technological advances might affect factory farming in the future. Here are the main things they mentioned:
- Widespread use of in ovo-sexing could mean farmers hatch only female chickens, preventing the culling of male chicks.
- R&D in aquaculture and insect farming will likely reduce their costs, increase intensification, and support the expansion of these industries. For example, we might see more productive fish and insect breeds, possibly with worse welfare for many (for the same reasons we see worse welfare for chickens that are more productive breeds).
- We may develop uses for factory farming other than food for humans or feed for other animals — for example, farming pigs for organ transplants.
- We might use gene-editing of animals to enhance either welfare or productivity (potentially at the expense of welfare).
- Increasing use of AI to make management decisions on factory farms could make farms more intensive and lower welfare, or could increase care and health for animals, depending on the details.
- We might make big strides in plant-based and cultivated (i.e. lab-grown) meat alternatives — which could displace factory farmed meat if they're able to compete on the market, meaning fewer animals are farmed.
The two developments that seem most likely to completely change the picture are the development of price, taste, and convenience-competitive alternatives to animal products and the development of transformative AI. We'll look at each of these in more detail below.
When might we develop really good alternatives to meat?
The development of a really good alternative to meat — one that is competitive with meat on price, taste, and convenience grounds — would be a game changer for factory farming.
We'd guess that, if there were more competetitive alternative products, it would be much easier to convince people to stop eating factory farmed meat — and as a result, to push for increased welfare on farms.[157]
There are three broad approaches to creating alternatives to animal products:
- Plant-based alternatives, made solely using ingredients from plants and fungi
- Fermentation methods (also known as acellular agriculture), which use microorganisms to create proteins usually found in animal products
- Cultivated meat (also known as cellular agriculture), which produces a product cellularly identical to animal meat through cultivating animal cells directly
Each of these approaches faces major challenges.
Plant-based and fermentation methods face difficult challenges in reaching parity with animal products on taste, texture, and on getting plant-based meat to cook like meat.[158] Fermentation methods produce individual proteins rather than complete products, but combining these animal proteins that aren't available in plants with plant-based products may overcome some of these challenges.
Ultimately, we'd guess that as long as there are substantial chemical differences between meat and its alternatives, there will be reasons not to switch. For example, people may have worries about health or chemical additives, or feel put off by differences in what the product looks like, feels like, or how it cooks. This is one reason why people are working on cultivated meat.
A 2020 report by David Humbird into cultured meat sparked controversy with its claims that there are severe technical challenges to growing cultivated meat at scale. Humbird's arguments include:
- The low growth rate of animal cells (especially compared to possible infectious microbial cells) means producers need to take expensive measures to ensure a sterile environment.
- It's difficult to transfer oxygen into, and waste out of, a bioreactor without rupturing animal cells, and this will limit the volume (and thus cost-efficiency) of bioreactors.
- Scaling up the industry producing the raw ingredients (amino acids and/or plant protein hydrolysates) will be extremely expensive.
We read the full report, along with some responses to it (by the Good Food Institute and by Rethink Priorities) — and ultimately were reasonably convinced that these challenges are real.
That doesn't mean that cultivated meat is a doomed project — it just means that without something radically changing (e.g. technological progress substantially speeding up in general), it might take a long time until we can use a competitive meat alternative to end factory farming.
Would a competitive meat alternative end factory farming, and if so — when?
There's more to consider than just the technology. If we have the technology for products that are competitive with meat on their price, taste, and convenience, would that lead to the end of factory farming? If so, how long would that take?
It's pretty unclear.
First, it's important to remember that making a real dent in meat consumption requires building up new infrastructure. We currently consume around 1 million tons of meat every single day. Building up a replacement for that would be a gigantic project. Humbird estimates that it would cost hundreds of millions of dollars to build a facility to replace less than 0.01% of the world's meat.[159]
There are also lots of other factors that might affect whether people will switch, like social norms, familiarity, food safety, and religion.[160] These factors are much harder to predict — for example, it's possible that the development of alternatives to animal products causes political polarisation and worse animal policy overall (although we'd guess that's less likely than the opposite).
So, what does all this mean for the future of meat production?
It's pretty hard to bring this information together into a meaningful prediction. We've seen two attempts to do this.
On Metaculus, a forecasting website, the aggregate of 268 predictions suggests there's a 12% chance of a 50% decline in global meat production by 2040.
Rethink Priorities brought together a panel of forecasters to predict how likely it is we'll have specifically cultivated meat by 2051. Aggregating their estimates suggests that, while there's an around 50% chance of us producing over 100,000 tons per year by then, there's more like a 9% chance of us producing over 50 million tons per year. (For comparison, we produced around 350 million tons of meat in 2022.)
But forecasting is really difficult when there are no clearly similar events to point to and when you're trying to predict low-probability events far into the future, so it's not clear what we should take away from this.
Perhaps more importantly, the estimates from Rethink Priorities were made assuming that there won't be some kind of transformative AI (and we'd guess that transformative AI wasn't much on the minds of the Metaculus forecasters either). And AI could massively change the picture.
How could AI affect factory farming?
As we've argued, we think there's a decent chance that we'll develop AI systems that are hugely transformative for society within the next few decades.
We think there's some chance that we could lose control of AI systems. But there's also a good chance we don't, and that developers are able to make AI systems that reliably do what their controllers want. If that's the case, even fairly autonomous AI systems will do roughly what humans want them to do — and so the way any AI system treats animals will be guided by the users' incentives, beliefs, and attitudes towards animals.
We'll probably find ways of using AI to make factory farming more efficient through the use of precision livestock farming — we'd guess this is negative overall (because it might lead to increased stocking densities, and it would reduce the price of meat, making it harder for alternative products to compete). But there could be positives too, such as reducing rates of disease. Animal advocates might be able to use AI systems to analyse CCTV footage from slaughterhouses to identify and prosecute violations. (For more on how AI might affect animals in the short term, see this article from Max Taylor, a researcher at Animal Charity Evaluators.)
We'll likely see these effects just with AI systems that are not too far from the current state of the art.
But how might the development of truly transformative AI — for example, AI systems that can automate a very large proportion of the things that humans can do — affect the picture?
Such systems would have huge economic effects. It's unclear exactly what these will be, but a simple model is that they would accelerate current economic trends and make society much richer — so we might see an acceleration of the trends we discussed above: per-capita meat consumption rising, peaking, and then declining as wealth increases.
More concretely, if AI systems are able to automate parts of the R&D processes, we'd see an acceleration of all the technological advances discussed above — in particular, the development of price, taste and convenience-competitive alternatives to animal products. As a result, we'd guess it's highly likely that we'll develop these alternatives this century.
This wouldn't necessarily bring the end of factory farming. We'd probably also see technological advances that reduce the price of meat, so there could be a long period of time where meat and alternatives are competing for customers. And as we discussed above, it could take decades to build the necessary infrastructure to replace animal agriculture. And there would still be social barriers preventing the end of factory farming — for example, we could end up in a situation where a large portion of society sticks to traditional meat products for religious reasons.
Overall though, the possibility of transformative AI makes us much more optimistic about the possibility of ending factory farming in the coming century — but it's by no means a certainty.
What might happen to factory farming in the very long-run future?
We've argued before that there are strong reasons to consider the interests of all future generations when assessing the scale of problems — and those arguments apply to future animals, as well as future humans.
That means that, to the extent that we can, we should try to look further ahead than just the coming century.
Here's a simple sketch of why this matters. If we could end factory farming this century, it would be a fantastic achievement. However, if factory farming were destined to end in the coming centuries anyway, or if factory farming were to reappear, the impact of this achievement would be significantly reduced.
So should we expect factory farming to remain in the long-term future (or reemerge), or not?
Of course we cannot know for sure — or anything close to sure. But there are some long-run factors we can consider to try to come to a provisional view.
One rule of thumb says that we should expect the future to be guided by the values, cultures, and beliefs of people alive today. We're all in a metaphorical tug of war about the direction of the future, and how society changes over time depends on the winners and losers of that game over the centuries.
It seems like right now things aren't trending towards an end to factory farming — in fact, factory farming is growing.
Of course, technological changes might affect this: perhaps the real barrier to change is just a lack of alternative products, and today's society cares enough about animals that it would end factory farming if those were developed.
But current evidence suggests that if a meat alternative was created tomorrow that was competitive on price, taste, and convenience with animal products, many people wouldn't switch — so if how the future goes is just an extrapolation of what society is like today, we won't see an end to factory farming.
A different rule of thumb looks to technology and economic efficiency. Ultimately, growing whole animals seems like an inefficient process.[161] So even if demand for meat remains high, eventually we should expect to develop far cheaper ways of producing meat. Then over time, we might expect people's values and desires to fall in line with these commercial incentives, and eating animal products will become a weird thing people used to do. Even more radically, perhaps people in the future won't need food for survival or entertainment — because maybe most people in the future will be digital.
This second line of argument seems more persuasive than the first — which suggests we shouldn't expect factory farming to last forever.
That said, there's some chance that society's values don't remain malleable, but instead become fixed or put permanently on a particular trajectory at a certain point in time, a possibility known as 'value lock-in'. It's been argued that the invention of artificial general intelligence could make it possible to fix the values with which society is governed over very long periods of time.
Ultimately, I think the chances of long-term value lock-in related to animals are very low. It seems that to prevent the drift of values over time, you would need a very controlling system like totalitarianism. We've written elsewhere about the chances of a perpetual totalitarian regime and (very roughly) estimated that there's around a 1 in 330 chance of a stable totalitarian regime arising in the next 100 years. The chances that such a perpetual regime will enforce particular norms about how we treat animals seems even smaller.
So, overall, over the very long-term, we'd guess that factory farming will come to an end.
There are promising ways of solving this problem
As in many areas, the best approaches to solving factory farming are probably hundreds of times more cost effective than others.
Below, we'll go through a few rules of thumb for finding the best approaches:
- Don't forget about technological advances (especially the plausible development of alternative proteins in the near future).
- Find interventions that offer more leverage.
- Find interventions that the animal agriculture industry won't fight.
- Don't cause harm.
- Work in neglected areas.
Later, we'll look at what you could do with your career to help make these happen.
First, we should try to find interventions that take a bet on alternative proteins. As we've argued, it seems like factory farming is going to increase over the next few decades unless we develop clear alternatives to animal products. But we think it's likely that we will develop these price, taste and convenience-competitive alternatives to meat within this century (not least because of the plausibility of transformative AI within the next few decades).
The development of these products in the near future is by no means guaranteed — and competitive products probably won't solve everything by themselves.
But this means there's an opportunity: it'll probably be much easier to reduce meat consumption and improve the lives of the remaining farmed animals once competitive alternatives are developed.
As a result, we think it's worth taking a bet: interventions whose theories of change assume that alternatives to meat will be developed to a point of market competitiveness seem likely to be more effective overall.
For example, you might work on finding ways to preemptively reduce barriers to the uptake of cultivated meat, such as finding ways to ensure cultivated meat adheres to religious dietary restrictions, or preventing a possible EU-wide ban on cultivated meat (which, if passed, could last decades or more).
Second, we should try to find interventions that offer more leverage — that is, ways of changing how a lot of resources are used, either via knock-on effects or directly.
One great example of this is corporate campaigns. These campaigns try to convince companies to commit to using higher-welfare animal products. Many companies will agree to make commitments without any public campaign, but if they don't, a campaign might include protests, negative advertising, and criticism on social media. These campaigns are a cost-effective way of helping improve the welfare of large numbers of farmed animals, as they're fairly cheap to run and can affect the entire supply chain of a large company.
These campaigns have been surprisingly successful. For example, companies such as Burger King, Unilever, and Chipotle have agreed to the Better Chicken Commitment, switching to higher-welfare slaughter methods and slower-growing breeds of broiler chicken (there's a similar campaign in Europe called the European Chicken Commitment). Companies also seem to stick to the pledges they make in similar campaigns — for cage-free campaigns for egg-laying hens, around 90% of companies fulfil their cage-free pledges (although we'd guess more work needs to be done to make this happen in the future).
Here's a breakdown of how the Better Chicken Commitment practices affect average chicken welfare:
Similarly, you might be able, using a small amount of resources, to get governments to act (and they have many, many more resources than even big companies). The EU is revising its animal welfare laws, and other European countries are also considering steps like banning caged hens. We think there are opportunities to help shape these reforms. In the US, it seems like ballot initiatives are almost as cost-effective as corporate campaigns. We're particularly excited about the Good Food Institute's work to leverage government funding for alternative proteins.
Third, we should look for interventions that the animal agriculture industry won't fight — or, at the very least, which don't require their support. This isn't always doable, but if you can find ways to improve the lives of animals that won't be fought, they're likely to be particularly cost effective.
One great example here is developing laws in countries with relatively high-welfare farms that restrict the import of low-welfare products, as this benefits both animals around the world and domestic farmers.
Another example is working on technological progress.
Some technological progress, such as technologies to prevent the conception of male chicks or immunocastration for piglets, could substantially improve the lives of farmed animals — and many have only small costs for farmers (e.g. in-ovo-sexing, which ensures all chicks born are female, increases the costs of egg production by around 1–3 cents per egg).
We'd also like to see research on ways of reducing keel bone fractures, as these are a major cause of suffering in laying hens, and may be worse in cage-free systems. More speculatively, we might be able to gene-edit animals to prevent them from feeling pain.
If we can find suffering-reducing technologies that are cheap to use, it may be easy to get farmers to use them (as we're seeing with in-ovo-sexing).
Fourth, importantly, we need to find solutions that don't accidentally cause harm.
As an example, we might be able to convince people not to eat beef on environmental grounds or by raising the price of beef through welfare interventions. But this might lead to people eating chicken instead — and not only do chickens live in much worse conditions, but they're smaller, so many more chickens are killed for the same amount of meat. The same problem arises even more so for switching to small fish and smaller invertebrates like shrimp.
Finding solutions that are very unlikely to cause harm is much harder than it sounds — there are plausible reasons why many of the solutions we've discussed above could cause harm. If you develop a technology that improves animal welfare (like immunocastration or in-ovo sexing), but this technology lowers costs for farmers, it also might decrease prices, increasing the demand for animal products and so increasing the number of animals in factory farms, resulting in more harm. Weighing up these effects is hard, and price-decreasing technologies may well end up being good overall — but because of the plausibility of harm, they're unlikely to be among the best approaches to solving factory farming, so we'd avoid working on them if you have other options.
As another example, corporate campaigns to get farms to switch to slower-growing breeds of chicken improves the welfare of the chickens, but these slower-growing breeds live longer, which might lead to more suffering overall. Corporate campaigns might also support humanewashing — convincing people that meat is high welfare when it's not, encouraging people to buy low-welfare products. Overall, we still think many corporate campaigns are worth doing — but it's important to investigate possible sources of harm when choosing what to work on.
In some cases, people have stopped their work because of this kind of risk. Anima International were campaigning to end live sales of carp in Poland. They became worried about carp being replaced with salmon, a carnivorous fish, and as a result increasing the number of fish farmed overall — and so ended their campaign. We think this is extremely commendable!
Some writers on animal welfare, such as Brian Tomasik go further and suggest avoiding most welfare interventions and instead focusing on improving slaughter — as slaughter improvements don't introduce other complicating factors like changing the length of time animals live.[162]
We're not saying you need to be certain that the intervention you work on doesn't cause harm — that's just not possible. But it's important to do what you can to think through the downsides and try as much as you can to avoid interventions that sound good and which might even do some good, but which are bad ideas overall because they may cause more harm.
Finally, if you can work in a particularly neglected sub-area of the issue, your solutions are more likely to be cost-effective overall. This is because solutions usually have diminishing returns to effort.
As we've seen, the vast majority of the animals in factory farms are fish and invertebrates (like crustaceans and insects). Work on these animals (like getting any aquatic welfare standards or finding better ways of slaughtering shrimp) seems pressing. We also think work to prevent the rise of insect factory farms seems particularly pressing.
Similarly, work in non-western countries is likely to be more cost-effective overall.
Work on factory farming is highly neglected
We've argued so far that factory farming is large in scale, and that there are promising ways of solving the problem. But work in this area is also pressing because it's so neglected that the impact of an additional person working on it or donating to efforts in the area will tend to be high.
Philanthropic spending on preventing factory farming is around $290 million a year[163] — which is similar to philanthropic spending on other issues we prioritise (like risks from AI and nuclear war), and over 100 times less than areas like global development (around $70 billion) or climate change (around $60 billion). Open Philanthropy, the largest single funder of farmed animal welfare work,[164] told us that they expect total spending in the area to grow to around $450 million a year over the next decade.
This spending corresponds to something like 1,750 to 2,000 people working on this problem full time, growing to something like 2,500 to 3,000 people over the next decade.[165]
There's also work being done in the private sector, especially in alternative proteins. There are something like 55,000 people total working for companies in the area (like Quorn, Gardein, and Beyond Meat). We're uncertain how to count these people — most of what they're doing is delivering products into supermarkets, which is helpful, but not really focused on advancing the field or ending factory farming. Only around 300 of these 55,000 roles are focused on cultivated or plant-based meat research.
If we focus only on work we think directly addresses the issue of factory farming (e.g. alternative protein research roles), spending from the private sector is more like $120 million per year, with around 750 people working on the problem.[165]
That means altogether, we'd estimate ~3,000 people are working on reducing harms from factory farming and around $410 million is dedicated to this issue.
Within that, there are areas that we see as particularly neglected. Around 10 people are working full time on insect farming and maybe around 20–30 on shrimp farming.[166] And it seems like Open Philanthropy's donors have decided not to fund work on invertebrate welfare, so these areas are particularly neglected in funding. We'd also guess that factory farming in developing countries tends to be more neglected.
How can we compare the pressingness of factory farming to existential risks?
We think that reducing risks to the continued existence of civilisation is a particularly pressing moral issue.
This is reflected in our list of the world's most pressing problems. Our top problems include:
All of these are prioritised so highly at least in part because we think they are existential risks.
So, in order to figure out how highly we should prioritise the problem of factory farming, we think it makes sense to try to compare it with existential risks.
This kind of comparison is going to be especially uncertain – this research is extremely challenging and there's not much existing work to draw on. We'd like to see more researchers try to tackle these questions, but for the time being we will try to sketch our own comparison here.
We'll start by trying to compare the scale of these problems: how much good would be achieved if we completely solved each of these problems?
To simplify things, let's try to compare factory farming directly with just the problem of nuclear weapons as an illustration of the kind of analysis needed.
We think the risk of nuclear war presents a large-scale problem. There are two reasons for this:
- A large nuclear war would have catastrophic immediate consequences, killing billions and causing unimaginable suffering — and it would reduce the size and probably quality of life of the population for many decades.
- Then there's a small but real chance (we'd guess something like 1 in 10,000) that such a war could lead to the complete collapse of civilisation, and even human extinction. This would have very long-run implications: there would be no more human civilisation, ever. Since the number of future individuals whose lives matter could be vast, the expected value of reducing risk to those lives could also be large.
Above, we looked at how many animals count morally the same as one human. We saw that from a welfarist perspective, there are two components to this:
- Animals are worthy of moral consideration if they are conscious, so we need to consider the chances that each animal is conscious.
- Animals have different welfare ranges (i.e. capacity for wellbeing). We looked into the most recent and most comprehensive research that's been done on this topic — Rethink Priorities' Moral Weight Project.
If we use the mean moral weights from the Moral Weights Project (that include both the welfare ranges and a weighting for the probability that each animal is conscious), and we multiply those weights by the number of animals of each species studied, we find that we kill the moral equivalent of 160 billion humans each year through factory farming, from a welfarist perspective.
There's huge uncertainty on this figure. Just looking at uncertainty in the welfare ranges, this figure might vary from 60 million to around 800 billion (using the 5th and 95th percentile estimates respectively). And that is before taking into account uncertainty that this is the right way to approach the question.
Still, let's compare that to the immediate consequences of a nuclear catastrophe (putting aside the long-run implications for now). A large-scale nuclear catastrophe could kill up to around 8 billion humans (the entire world population), and do so once — not every year.
Moreover, the suffering caused by the way we treat animals seems plausibly even worse than the suffering a nuclear war would cause its survivors.
This suggests the scale of factory farming is larger than (or perhaps similar to) the scale of the immediate consequences of a large nuclear war. Personally, I'd guess that, morally speaking, the scale of factory farming over the course of a few decades is something like 100 times larger than the scale of the immediate consequences of a large nuclear war.
It's much harder to compare the scale of factory farming with the immediate consequences plus the potentially ultra long-term consequences of nuclear war arising from the existential risk that such a war might pose.
We argued above that some kind of value lock-in that perpetuates factory farming into the very long-run future seems highly unlikely, and that, over the very long run, we expect factory farming to end. That said, we might expect the effects of our actions on the welfare or number of farmed animals to persist for decades, and it could be centuries.
How you compare this with the long-run effects of nuclear war depends on how much you buy the arguments for thinking existential risks are top priorities due to their scale.
In short, those arguments say that:
- We should care about how the lives of future individuals go. (If animals are worthy of moral consideration, or if we should care about digital minds, we need to consider them too).
- The number of future individuals whose lives matter could be vast.
- Those individuals' lives are likely to be good overall — for example, with more flourishing than suffering (or whatever is relevant for a good life).
- This means that it's better for these individuals to be able to exist than for the universe to be empty. So there aren't just a lot of lives in the future, there's a lot of moral value in the future that we would lose if we went extinct or permanently reduced our potential as a species.
- The expected scale of existential risk reduction, which can be calculated by multiplying the size of the risk by the value of the future, is therefore high. (This is just about the expected scale of reducing existential risks — in our article on existential risks, we also talk about the neglectedness and tractability of doing so. Many people view lower tractability as a reason not to prioritise existential risk reduction.)
We argue for the first two of these claims in our article on longtermism and think they are very likely to be true.
Whether future individuals' lives are likely to be good seems much harder to answer — we'd guess the answer is yes, but that's highly uncertain. In my view, this uncertainty substantially decreases the relative importance of existential risk reduction compared to other concerns.
The fourth claim (it's good for individuals with good lives to exist) is controversial, but our guess is that it's true. Read more about the arguments here.
The final claim — that the expected value of the future is high — relies on the idea that existential risk is going to be much lower in the future (otherwise, the expected number of future people ends up relatively small).
Finally, thinking in terms of expectations is a theoretical ideal, not a practical methodology. Making explicit estimates of expected scale (like by multiplying the size of a plausibly existential risk by the value of the future) is sometimes useful as a method, but we should also look for useful rules of thumb and robust arguments, or even use gut intuitions which can incorporate implicit understanding from experience rather than (just) explicit reasoning. And it's not clear that all rules of thumb — even ones focused on improving the long-term future — suggest the scale of existential risk is larger than that of factory farming.[167]
Given all this, I think a reasonable position to take is that we should think of nuclear war as a large-scale problem for both its short-run consequences and the existential risk it poses. If that's right, then it'd be reasonable to think of these effects as comparable in scale — so that the existential risk's contribution to the scale of the problem is between 10% and 90% of the total scale of the problem of nuclear war. Combining that with my view that the short-run effects of factory farming are plausibly 100 times more important than the short-run effects of nuclear war suggests that factory farming is overall larger in scale.
That said, while comparing factory farming to existential risks in general is extremely difficult, and it's plausible factory farming is a larger-scale problem than nuclear war, we do think that factory farming seems smaller in scale than the existential risk posed by AI — as the existential risk from AI seems substantially larger than that posed by nuclear war.
As we've argued, factory farming is also highly neglected. It seems like it's currently less neglected than preventing an AI-related catastrophe, but more neglected than most other issues we prioritise, like nuclear weapons or preventing catastrophic pandemics. We'd also guess that preventing an AI-related catastrophe is becoming less neglected faster than factory farming, so within a few years factory farming may be the most neglected of these areas.
We're not really sure how to compare the solvability of factory farming to existential risks. Helping some animals — for example, through corporate campaigns — seems far more tractable than most ways of reducing existential risks, but it's only addressing a small part of the overall problem. Large-scale changes to factory farming like ending big chunks of the industry seem much harder right now, maybe harder than substantially reducing existential risks, but as we've argued, we think it could become much easier as technology advances — and there are things we can do now to lay the groundwork. Overall, factory farming seems similarly solvable to other problems we prioritise (although we're highly uncertain).
It's worth underlining again that these comparisons are hugely difficult and under-researched, so no one should take this analysis as definitive. But, putting the above reasoning together into a best guess, I have come to think that factory farming is likely more pressing than smaller-scale existential risks like nuclear war, but less pressing than the plausibly much larger existential risk posed by AI. 80,000 Hours as an organisation continues to rank nuclear war as more pressing than factory farming, but there's significant uncertainty and ongoing debates about these topics.
What are the major arguments against this problem being (especially) pressing?
We just gave one major argument: that factory farming probably doesn't influence the long-run future, whereas existential risks do. If you find the arguments for focusing on issues that can affect the long-run future persuasive, that means that if an existential risk is substantial, it's plausibly a larger-scale problem than factory farming.
Here are a few other reasons you could have for prioritising other issues above factory farming:
- You might think that the wellbeing of each animal matters much less than the wellbeing of each human. If you think the difference is big enough, then you'll think the scale of this problem isn't as large (in terms of moral importance) as the scale of problems that affect current generations of humans, like global health or any imminent risks from pandemics, war, and AI.
- You might agree with prioritising work on the long-run future, but think that there are other ways of affecting the long-run future other than working on existential risks — some people prioritise improving the trajectory of civilisation over preserving its existence. For example, you might think the way we treat digital sentience could have a bigger impact on the long-run future than the way we treat animals, if you expect there to be more digital minds than animal minds. If so, this suggests that you should work on digital sentience (or another issue that seems like it could affect the long-run future) instead.
There are also some reasons that you might be very pessimistic about our ability to make progress on ending factory farming — at least in a way that doesn't worsen other issues:
- You might worry that promoting concern for other beings increases risks of astronomical future suffering. This suggests you should work on s-risks instead.
- You might think that work on farmed animal welfare could make lives worse for wild animals.
- You might think that the lack of growth in veganism and pro-animal attitudes over the past decades (since an initial surge in popularity in the West) suggests that moral attitudes to animals are highly resistant to change. If you're also sceptical about technological change ending factory farming, you might just think the problem is intractable.
What can you do to help?
When people think about working in animal welfare, they might picture looking after chickens in a sanctuary or handing out leaflets in a shopping mall.
But there are options that we think can achieve many times more impact than either of these options. A really high-impact job that's working on reducing factory farming would focus on the ways of solving the problem that we discussed above.
As a result, the main options we recommend in this area are:
- Earning to give
- Helping to run nonprofits
- Founding something new
- Government and policy
- Corporate campaigning and activism
- Scientific research
- Strategy research and grantmaking
We'll go into some detail about each of these below.
If you're moving into the area for the first time, or early in your career, you could also try:
- Joining a student fellowship or group (for example, the Alt Protein Project student groups, The Reducetarian Fellowship, the New Roots Leadership program, or the Southeast Asia Farm Animal Welfare Fellowship
- Attending a conference that's open to newcomers, but that's attended by most of the main organisations in the space (for example, AVA or CARE). We've also been told that, if you can get a spot, EA Globals are some of the easiest places for people just starting out in the area to speak one-on-one with organisational leadership. (At purely animal-focused conferences, leadership figures are too popular!)
We'd also recommend taking a look at Animal Advocacy Careers as well as Hive, a Slack workspace and newsletter focused on farmed animal advocacy.
If you already have experience, it might be worth looking at what the main skill bottlenecks are to making progress on the problem in order to figure out where you can contribute best. When we spoke to people we know working on solving factory farming, they told us the main bottlenecks are:
- Funding
- Management and leadership
- Government and policy expertise
- Entrepreneurship and starting new organisations
We expect these to change over time, so they're a less useful guide if you think you should currently be spending time building career capital and only aiming to have an impact later (which we often recommend for people who are early in their careers).
Of course, no matter what your job is, if you have more wealth than you need you can help by donating a portion of your income to the most cost-effective animal charities you can find. (See here for a few recommendations.)
Earning to give
As we mentioned, there's very little funding for factory farming relative to many other causes.
So one of the best ways to help might be by earning to give, which means taking any job that's higher paying in order to donate more.
Our top recommendations for earning to give — because they can pay so much — are:
These paths are highly competitive, but if you're exceptionally successful, you could earn millions of dollars a year. If you donate most of that, that would mean increasing the funding for the whole cause area by something like 1% by yourself! If you take the time to make sure you're donating to particularly effective opportunities, your impact could be even higher than that suggests.
We'd be particularly excited about people earning to give to support invertebrate welfare (e.g. insects, shrimp, and other crustaceans) because these areas aren't currently being funded by large donors like Open Philanthropy.
Helping to run nonprofits
Many of the organisations working on the most cost-effective solutions are nonprofits.
These organisations need people to help run them. That might mean working in management, HR, finance, accounting, law, fundraising, software, operations, marketing, communications, and more.
According to Animal Advocacy Careers, nonprofits working on ending factory farming currently find it hardest to hire for leadership and fundraising positions. So if you're a good fit for one of those, you might find your skills are especially useful.
The best way to get started if you don't already have experience is probably by finding any role that will let you start learning relevant skills — even if that's not initially at a high-impact organisation.
To learn more, including more information on how to get started, take a look at our article on organisation-building skills.
You could also look at:
- Management and leadership skills (by Animal Advocacy Careers)
- Fundraising skills (by Animal Advocacy Careers)
- Our career reviews of software engineering and operations management in high-impact organisations.
Seren Kell
Seren did a degree in biochemistry and went straight into working in alternative proteins. But she didn’t go into research. Instead, she’s the head of the SciTech team at the Good Food Institute Europe. They are helping build the field of alternative proteins by identifying the barriers to growth and removing them — for example, by building funding and helping founders find collaborators. We’d guess this is even higher impact than directly working on alternative protein research because it’s so high leverage.
Founding something new
Founding something is a difficult path — but, if you succeed, it can be hugely impactful.
There are two broad routes here outside founding a company for earning to give:
- Founding a new nonprofit focusing on a gap in what's needed to tackle factory farming
- Founding a for-profit company that helps solve the problem — with the current best bet being alternative proteins (especially if you can find investment that wouldn't otherwise be spent on alternative protein research)
Even if it doesn't work out, you'll probably learn a huge amount — so this can also be a great route for career capital.
If you're starting a nonprofit, one option is to join an incubator, such as Charity Entrepreneurship or, if you're in Southeast Asia, Welfare Matters' Farmed Animal Welfare Incubator.
If you're interested in founding an alternative protein startup, take a look at these resources from the Good Food Institute. The Good Food Institute also offers a mentorship programme for alternative protein entrepreneurs, a database of accelerators and incubators, and a community and events.
To learn more about this career path, read our career review on founding impactful organisations.
Andrés Jiménez Zorrilla
Andrés probably wouldn’t have guessed his career would end up focused on shrimp. While he was always interested in animal welfare, his early career was pretty normal — he studied economics at university and then went to work in real estate. In 2020, he pivoted his career through the Charity Entrepreneurship Incubation Program, and as a result he cofounded the Shrimp Welfare Project, which to date has helped over one billion shrimp.
Government and policy
There are two broad areas for government and policy work on factory farming:
- Improving welfare standards on farms — as we mentioned earlier, there are lots of exciting opportunities for legislative reform
- Removing barriers to and leveraging government support for alternative proteins — most of this work is currently carried out by the Good Food Institute and its affiliates around the world
Working in policy might mean working in the executive branch, lobbying from the outside, or possibly even running for office.
Our article on policy and political skills goes into more detail, including a bunch of ideas about how to get started in the area.
Corporate campaigning and activism
Corporate campaigns — like those we mentioned above working on improving the lives of caged chickens — are one of the most cost-effective ways people have found of improving welfare for currently farmed animals.
So learning how to effectively carry out these campaigns is a particularly useful skill set, especially if you can then go on to run entire teams or organisations of campaigners.
We haven't looked into this area much, but we'd guess the best way to get started would be to volunteer with an organisation doing corporate campaigns, like The Humane League.
Leah Garcés
Leah Garcés initially thought that the best way to help animals would be by becoming a vet. But while she was studying for a master’s degree at King’s College London, she discovered the world of professional activism. Her first job out of college, at the age of 22, was as an international campaign manager at Compassion in World Farming. She’s now the president of Mercy for Animals, an organisation focused on campaigning for the welfare of farmed animals.
Scientific and engineering research
We think there are opportunities for scientists to help reduce factory farming by:
- Developing alternative proteins
- Working in animal welfare science
This work will probably require you to have a relevant degree. In both fields, biology or chemistry undergraduate degrees are useful; you can also do research into animal welfare with philosophy or neuroscience backgrounds.
About half of alternative protein job postings say they require a relevant postgraduate degree — either a relevant PhD or a master's with multiple year's additional industry experience. According to the Good Food Institute, relevant areas include: mycology, plant biology, molecular biology, cell biology, biochemistry, food science, genetic engineering, chemical engineering, mechanical engineering, bioengineering, tissue engineering, and materials engineering.
To get started on an alternative protein research career path, we'd recommend this newcomer's guide from the Good Food Institute.
There are also lots of unanswered questions in animal welfare science. What are the relevant indicators for animal consciousness? How much pain do animals feel on farms in different situations? We have some vague answers to these questions, but better answers could importantly guide people's actions — and we know far less for some animals, like fish and invertebrates.
For this article, we leaned heavily on the work of the Welfare Footprint Project, who carefully analyse the effects of things like the Better Chicken Commitment or banning gestation crates for sows. On insects, we're excited about the work of the Arthropoda Foundation.
Most research in this area happens in academia (and even at organisations like the Welfare Footprint Project, most researchers have an academic background) — which again means you'll likely need a relevant postgraduate degree. For more on academic careers, read our article on how to become an academic researcher.
There's other potentially useful research, such as the development of in-ovo sexing and immunocastration. More speculatively, The Far Out Initiative is researching ways of genetically engineering animals who don't suffer — I'd guess that at least some people should be engaging in this sort of research, but it's much less likely to pan out than the other research we've mentioned in this section.
If you're interested in a career in research and just getting started, we'd suggest reading our article on building research skills.
Strategy research and grantmaking
These roles involve figuring out what we should be doing to best help farmed animals, and then making that happen.
This might mean something like economics research in academia looking at the price elasticity of animal products to figure out where cost-increasing interventions should focus to have the biggest impact (or where cost-decreasing interventions could cause substantial harm), or becoming a grantmaker at a foundation looking to fund solutions to factory farming.
For academic research, you'll want to pursue a PhD in economics, or get a degree in public policy or maybe philosophy. Doing similar research at a think tank or nonprofit might not require an advanced degree, but it's probably still useful.
For becoming a grantmaker, you should probably start by doing any other work in animal welfare, building up your expertise and connections. (Read more about how to become a grantmaker.)
You could also try testing your fit for research and strategy roles by doing a research project in your spare time or funded by a grant, perhaps on a topic from Open Philanthropy's list of social science research topics for animal welfare.
Lewis Bollard
After graduating with a law degree, Lewis started out his career as a consultant, before moving to work as a litigation fellow at The Humane Society of the United States. He now leads Open Philanthropy’s farm animal welfare grantmaking.
Find vacancies on our job board
Find vacancies on our job boardThere are also other job boards that you might find helpful, including:
- Animal Advocacy Careers' job board covers jobs in a range of areas we think are particularly impactful.
- Alt Protein.Jobs and Alt Protein Careers focus on alt protein jobs, while ForceBrands and Indie Bio cover a wider range of related jobs (which may be useful for career capital).
- Vegan Job Board and VeganJobs focus on advocacy and nonprofits.
Key organisations
The main funders and grantmaking organisations (donating $500,000+ a year) are:
- Open Philanthropy — the largest funder in the area
- The Navigation Fund, which works primarily on influencing dominant institutions to care more about farm animal welfare
- Focus Philanthropy, which focuses solely on reducing the harms of animal agriculture
- The Craigslist Fund (yes, that craigslist), which also focuses on factory farming
- Farmed Animal Funders, a decentralised funding collaborative which helps funders make decisions about animal welfare donations
- EA Funds, a platform for moving money to particularly cost-effective and altruistically impactful projects, which has an animal welfare fund
- Animal Charity Evaluators, which evaluates animal charities and compares their effectiveness, influencing around $10m a year
- The Food Animal Concerns Trust, which directs grants to farmers and others to support humane farming methods
There are more animal grantmakers on this list.
Organisations working on alternatives to animal products:
- The Good Food Institute works to support the industry in the US. They help with field-building through grants, infrastructure, research, and bringing in private sector funding. They also work in policy, leveraging funding for alternative proteins and removing policy barriers.
- The Good Food Institute has affiliate organisations around the world: GFI Asia Pacific, GFI Brasil, GFI Europe, GFI Israel, and GFI India.
- There are thousands of companies working on some kind of animal product alternatives. We'd suggest looking at Alt Protein.Jobs and Alt Protein Careers for jobs in the area.
Some particularly relevant governmental and intergovernmental organisations:
- The European Commission, in particular the Directorate-General Sante (unit G3 is responsible for animal welfare and unit E2 is responsible for regulations around novel foods, including alternative proteins), the Directorate-General Agriculture (unit E3 is responsible for animal products) and the Directorate-General Research and Innovation (unit B2 is resposible for research and innovation in alternative proteins).
- The US Department of Agriculture is responsible for most animal welfare policy in the US.
- The UK Department for Environment Food and Rural Affairs is responsible for most animal welfare policy in the UK.
- The UK Animal Sentience Committee examines UK government policy to see whether it fully considers the welfare needs of animals as sentient beings.
- The World Organisation for Animal Health focuses on animal disease control and has 183 member states.
Lobbying and campaigning organisations, focusing on both the government and corporations. Here are some of the top organisations around the world:
- The Humane League conducts corporate campaigns, with a particular focus on farmed chickens. They founded the Open Wing Alliance, a global anti-cage coalition.
- Mercy for Animals work on undercover investigations of factory farms, government lobbying, and corporate campaigns.
- The Albert Schweitzer Foundation lobbies the German government and corporations, as well as working on class action lawsuits and talking to consumers. They also have an organisation in Poland.
- Animal Equality does investigations of farms, corporate outreach, and legal advocacy, as well as public education projects.
- Eurogroup for Animals is a pan-European organisation focusing on EU legislation.
- Wakker Dier runs campaigns for farm animal welfare in the Netherlands.
- Fórum Animal works on animal welfare in Brazil.
- Anima International focuses on investigating farms and corporate campaigns, working in several European countries.
- Observatorio de Beinestar Animal works on corporate and government lobbying in Spain.
- Sinergia Animal does corporate outreach, policy work, and investigations in South America and South East Asia.
- The Accountability Board engages in shareholder activism.
- Çiftlik Hayvanlarını Koruma Derneği conducts corporate, individual, and media outreach in Türkiye.
- Legal Impact for Chickens does corporate outreach and litigation work in the US.
- Compassion in World Farming conducts a wide variety of campaigns in the UK focused on ending factory farming.
- Animals Aoteoroa campaigns on chicken welfare in New Zealand.
- Voters for Animal Rights helps elect US political candidates who support animal welfare reform.
Organisations focused on dietary change:
- Veganuary has played a significant role in promoting vegan food in the UK and now has campaigns across the EU, India, South Africa, and the US.
- Dansk Vegetarisk Forening promotes plant-based products in Denmark.
- China Vegan Society focuses on vegan movement-building in China.
Meta organisations, which help build the animal movement. Here are some of the top organisations around the world:
- Hive runs an active slack community and public events for the animal advocacy movement.
- Ambitious Impact runs programs like the Charity Entrepreneurship incubation programme, starting new charities focused on global health and animal welfare.
- Faunalytics conducts useful research for animal advocates.
- New Roots Institute educates students in the US about animal agriculture.
- Catalyst is building an animal welfare movement specifically in Thailand.
- Welfare Matters is building an animal advocacy movement across Southeast Asia.
- Animal Alliance Asia is also focused on creating a cross-Asia animal welfare community.
- Animal Advocacy Africa is trying to build an animal advocacy movement in Africa.
- Rethink Priorities and Animal Ask do research that tries to resolve important strategic questions for animal advocacy.
- Animal Advocacy Careers provides online advice, a job board, and other resources to help people have high-impact animal advocacy careers.
- For a more comprehensive list covering organisations in a range of countries across the world, take a look at Animal Charity Evaluators's List of Farmed Animal Advocacy Organisations.
Organisations focused on fish and crustacean welfare:
- Fish Welfare Initiative works with farmers in India, China, and the Philippines to improve welfare standards.
- fair-fish international association gathers information on fish welfare into the fair-fish database.
- FishEthoGroup promotes research and gives consultancy and training on fish welfare.
- Aquatic Life Institute helps promote animal welfare standards in fisheries and aquaculture through a certification campaign and policy work.
- Crustacean Compassion campaigns for the legal protection and humane treatment of decapod crustaceans in the UK.
- Shrimp Welfare Project aims to promote the adoption of electrical stunning technology in the shrimp industry, as well as working with farmers in India and Vietnam on welfare standards, and conducting research.
Other nonprofit organisations working in the area:
- Insect farming and insect welfare charities, such as The Insect Institute and The Insect Welfare Research Society.
- The Welfare Footprint Project is trying to quantify and map animal welfare across different living conditions.
- Innovate Animal Ag works on finding technological solutions to animal welfare problems, like in-ovo sexing and on-farm hatching.
- The Humane Slaughter Association helps farmers slaughter animals in higher-welfare ways.
- Global Food Partners are a consultancy to help companies in Asia meet cage-free goals.
Learn more
Top recommendations
- Animal Advocacy Careers provides articles, advice, and a job board to help you find a career to try to end factory farming
- Podcast: Lewis Bollard on the 7 most promising ways to end factory farming, and whether AI is going to be good or bad for animals
- Podcast: Seren Kell on the research gaps holding back alternative proteins from mass adoption
Further recommendations
- Other effective animal advocacy resources from Rethink Priorities
- Open Philanthropy's report on the treatment of animals in factory farms
- Leah Garcés on turning adversaries into allies to change the chicken industry
- Lewis Bollard on ending factory farming as soon as possible and big wins against factory farming and how they happened
- Bruce Friedrich makes the case that inventing outstanding meat replacements is the most effective way to help animals
- Meghan Barrett on challenging our assumptions about insects
- How exactly clean meat is created and the advances needed to get it into every supermarket, according to food scientist Marie Gibbons
- Sharon Nuñez and Jose Valle on going undercover to expose animal cruelty, get rabbit cages banned, and reduce meat consumption
- Andrés Jiménez Zorrilla on the Shrimp Welfare Project
- Bob Fischer on comparing the welfare of humans, chickens, pigs, octopuses, bees, and more
- Sébastien Moro on the most insane things fish can do
- ^
Data on the proportion of animals in factory farms is hard to find — not least because the definition of factory farm is fuzzy. In this article, we’ll try to explain how animals are usually treated in the vast majority of commercial farms.
We can get some data on this question from the United States Environmental Protection Agency, which talks about “concentrated animal feeding operations” (CAFOs), defined by the USDA as farms where animals are confined for 45 days or more in any 12-month period, and where the number of animals confined reaches a certain threshold, depending on the species, and where wastewater is managed in a certain way.
We’d guess that almost all CAFOs are factory farms, but that many non-CAFOs are also factory farms, either because they have animals in high-density conditions but have few animals, or because they have good wastewater management — so they don’t have the sort of environmental or pollution impact that the EPA cares about.
The Sentience Institute combined EPA data on CAFOs with USDA Census of Agriculture data on total animal populations (see the numbers in this spreadsheet to find the % of animals in factory farms in the US.
They found that 98% of land animals in the US were factory-farmed in 2017:
- 99.96% of broiler (meat) chickens
- 98% of egg-laying hens
- 99.9% of turkeys
- 98% of pigs
- 70% of cows
Unfortunately, there’s little data on the rest of the world. Based on our understanding of the regulatory landscape, we’d guess the situation is better in the EU but at least as bad elsewhere.
We’d also guess that the situation for fish is even worse than for broiler chickens. As far as we can tell there is both very little regulation about fish welfare and very little consumer demand for high-welfare fish.
We discuss more about how each animal is commonly treated below.
If the number of animals is roughly proportional to population, keeping in mind that 90% of animals in the EU are factory farmed (which we’d guess is an underestimate) and 98% of animals in the US and elsewhere are factory farmed, then approximately 97.5% of animals globally are factory farmed.
For more discussion, see How many animals are factory farmed by Hannah Ritchie at Our World in Data.
- ^
Rethink Priorities researcher Saulius Šimčikas collated estimates of global captive vertebrate numbers. We used these estimates for this article.
We chose this research because it’s a collation of figures from the most widely used source — the Food and Agriculture Organization of the United Nations statistics database, FAOSTAT. Where FAOSTAT data was unavailable Šimčikas used reasonable sources and noted his uncertainty, giving ranges instead of point estimates. For example, for the number of farmed fish, Šimčikas based his estimate on data from Fishcount (who later published that data under peer review) and noted its high uncertainty.
Šimčikas noted issues with FAOSTAT and discussed at least one of these with the Food and Agriculture Organization who agreed there was a mistake.
Overall, this source seems comprehensive,fairly reliable, and unlikely to be biased in any particular direction (even though Šimčikas was an animal advocacy researcher when he wrote the post).
- ^
Reliable estimates on the number of invertebrates in farms are harder to find than estimates for vertebrates. We relied on four sources:
- Insects raised for food and feed — global scale, practices, and policy by Abraham Rowe, which was based off production tonnage estimates completed by Barclays, the International Platform for Insects as Food and Feed (IPIFF), and other researchers, as well as conversations with farmers and the insect industry.
- Shrimp: the animals most commonly used and killed for food production by Daniela Waldhorn and Elisa Autric, which was based off production tonnage estimates from the Food and Agriculture Organization of the United Nations statistics database, FAOSTAT.
- Snails used for human consumption: The case of meat and slime by Daniela Waldhorn, also based off FAOSTAT.
- Data on non-shrimp crustaceans from Fishcount.
- ^
In general, animal welfare rules and standards are stronger in European countries (in particular Austria and Sweden) than elsewhere in the world.
For more details see the Animal Protection Index which ranks countries by their animal protection policies, and Why did the EU lead the world on farm animal welfare and how can it lead again? by Lewis Bollard.
At the same time, compliance rates in the EU range from around 90% to around 20%, depending on the regulation (and the way in which compliance rates are estimated) — for a collation of work on this topic, see Do countries comply with EU animal welfare laws? by Neil Dullaghan, a researcher at Rethink Priorities.
Together, this suggests that European standards for conditions are likely substantially better than the actual conditions in which the vast majority of farmed animals — in European countries and elsewhere — are kept.
- ^
We kill around 5 to 70 trillion wild marine animals every year (mainly shrimp), and between 100 trillion and 10 quadrillion smaller invertebrates, primarily through the use of pesticides. For completeness, we could also consider human effects on nematodes and zooplankton, which are likely extremely large in scale, but these tiny animals are generally poorly studied and everything about them (how many there are, how humans affect them, and whether they feel pain) is extremely uncertain.
- ^
According to a scientific opinion from the European Food and Safety Administration:
The EU is one of the world’s biggest producers of poultry meat with around 6 billion broiler chickens being reared for meat every year resulting in 13.3 million tonnes of poultry meat. Overall, broiler farming in the EU is characterised by high intensification with the majority of birds reared indoor, at high stocking densities and where birds are bred for rapid muscular growth, and slaughtered within 28–42 days of age.
Søren Saxmose Nielsen, et al. “Welfare of Broilers on Farm.” EFSA Journal, vol. 21, no. 2, 1 Feb. 2023, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2023.7788.
- ^
A systematic review of poultry production diseases reported an average ascites incidence of 5% in flocks (see Table 2 of Jones et al., 2018), based on two studies of broiler chickens in a lab setting and one survey of ascites mortality rates in the UK in the 1990s.
Jones, P. J., et al. “A Review of the Financial Impact of Production Diseases in Poultry Production Systems.” Animal Production Science, vol. 59, no. 9, 2019, p. 1585, https://doi.org/10.1071/an18281.
- ^
According to Granquit et al., 2019, which surveyed Norwegian farms
The aim of this study was to explore lameness and the associations between lameness and health/production measures of animal welfare in commercial broiler production, using the Welfare Quality® protocol for broilers. A total of 50 flocks were included in the sample and farm visits were conducted for lameness scoring at a mean age of 28.9 days… 19% of the birds showed moderate-to-severe lameness, which was associated with several production or health and welfare observations including feather cleanliness and condemnations as unfit for human consumption at slaughter.
For more on lameness in broiler chickens, see Schuck-Paim et al., 2022.
Granquist, E. G., et al. “Lameness and Its Relationship with Health and Production Measures in Broiler Chickens.” Animal, vol. 13, no. 10, 21 Mar. 2019, pp. 2365–2372, https://doi.org/10.1017/s1751731119000466.
Schuck-Paim, Cynthia, et al. “Quantifying the Welfare Impacts of Lameness in Broiler Chickens.” Quantifying Pain in Broiler Chickens: Impact of the Better Chicken Commitment and Adoption of Slower-Growing Breeds on Broiler Welfare, edited by Cynthia Schuck-Paim and Wladimir J. Alonso, Welfare Footprint Project, 1 May 2022. (Read the chapter as a google doc).
- ^
For example, the minimum allowed stocking density for free-range chickens in the UK is 27.5kg/m².
If we assume broiler chickens weigh around 3kg (which is probably slightly heavier than the average broiler), then that’s 9.2 chickens per square metre, or 0.1 square metres of space.
The Better Chicken Commitment allows for a density up to 30kg/m² (6lbs / sq ft), resulting in slightly less space per cage-free chicken.
- ^
Approximately 50% of heavy broilers (3.6 to 3.8 kg) reared on commercial farms in the Southeastern United States (US) present with some degree of [footpad dermatitis]. Furthermore, studies in Europe showed [footpad dermatitis] in 58% of the assessed commercial broilers. Besides on the feet, similar types of contact dermatitis can occur on hocks (hock burns) and the abdomen.
Freeman, Nathan, et al. “Remedying Contact Dermatitis in Broiler Chickens with Novel Flooring Treatments.” Animals, vol. 10, no. 10, 28 Sept. 2020, p. 1761, https://doi.org/10.3390/ani10101761.
- ^
St-Pierre et al., 2003, estimated economic losses due to heat stress. As part of their analysis, they estimated the number of hours of heat stress pear year for poultry in various US states (see table 10) — this varied from around 100 hours per year (1% of the year) to around 1,000 hours per year (11% of the year), with an average of 668 hours / year (7.5% of the year).
For more on heat stress in broiler chickens, see Schuck-Paim et al., 2022. Schuck-Paim et al. note that the data in St-Pierre et al., 2003, is based on weather observations, which may not accurately capture the actual environment inside farms. They instead look at studies of bird behaviour — in particular, the frequency of panting to cool down — and conclude that:
An average proportion of 10 to 40% of birds within a typical flock of fast-growing broilers, growing near the maximum allowed density for the housing type used (close or open-sided), will be affected by heat stress in the last week of the 6-weeks growth cycle.
St-Pierre, N.R., et al. “Economic Losses from Heat Stress by US Livestock Industries.” Journal of Dairy Science, vol. 86, June 2003, pp. E52–E77, https://doi.org/10.3168/jds.s0022-0302(03)74040-5.
Schuck-Paim, Cynthia, et al. “The welfare impact of heat stress in modern breeds of broiler chickens.” Quantifying Pain in Broiler Chickens: Impact of the Better Chicken Commitment and Adoption of Slower-Growing Breeds on Broiler Welfare, edited by Cynthia Schuck-Paim and Wladimir J. Alonso, Welfare Footprint Project, 1 May 2022. (Read the chapter as a google doc).
- ^
In order to determine the prevalence and risk factors for necrotic enteritis in broilers, a cross-sectional survey was conducted among 857 farms, rearing broilers for nine UK poultry companies… During 2001, 32.8% of the respondents indicated that they had
observed a case of necrotic enteritis (95% confidence interval, 29.1 to 36.8) in at least one flock. The disease was most often reported during the months October to February. The point prevalence (necrotic enteritis occurrence in the most recently reared flock) reported by farm managers was 12.3% (95% confidence interval, 9.8 to 15.2).Hermans, P. G., and K. L. Morgan. “Prevalence and Associated Risk Factors of Necrotic Enteritis on Broiler Farms in the United Kingdom; a Cross-Sectional Survey.” Avian Pathology, vol. 36, no. 1, Feb. 2007, pp. 43–51, https://doi.org/10.1080/03079450601109991.
- ^
A clinico-epidemiological study was therefore conducted at the District Veterinary Hospital, Kishoreganj, Bangladesh during October-November 2019 to determine the overall disease prevalence, prescription patterns, and disease associated factors in different bird types… Visceral gout (42.4%), coccidiosis (49.2%), and colibacillosis (24.2%) were the most frequent disease in broiler, Sonali, and layers, respectively.
Islam, Meherjan, et al. “Common Chicken Diseases in Kishoreganj, Bangladesh: Estimation through the Veterinary Hospital-Based Passive Surveillance System.” Advances in Animal and Veterinary Sciences, vol. 9, no. 11, 1 Jan. 2021, https://doi.org/10.17582/journal.aavs/2021/9.11.1951.1958.
- ^
According to a scientific opinion from the European Food and Safety Administration:
The majority of broiler breeders will normally have restricted access to feed from about 7–10 days of age until the end of life. The severity of the feed restriction is high during the rearing period where the restriction level reduces the feed quantity down to 20–25% of what a broiler breeder pullet would eat if having ad libitum access to feed.
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose et al. “Welfare of Broilers on Farm.” EFSA Journal, vol. 21, no. 2, 1 Feb. 2023, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2023.7788.
- ^
According to an opinion from the UK Government Animal Welfare Committee:
At catching, carrying, collecting and loading, birds are exposed to welfare risks (for example injury, sudden large changes in temperature)… Due to the construction of feeder and watering systems in broiler and pullet barns, at thinning, feed and water are typically withdrawn from all birds, including those that will remain.
The opinion, which can be found here, goes into much more detail on the pre-slaughter process for poultry in the UK.
- ^
Some hens are not stunned at all: 2.3% of total slaughtered meat chickens are not pre-stunned in the UK, according to 2022 data from Food Standards Agency (see the table on p.12).
Others are not effectively stunned, leaving them conscious for bleeding and slaughter. After assessing 10 Dutch farms and 10 Italian farms, de Jong et al., 2010, found that 7.1% of birds in the Dutch farms were not adequately stunned when exiting the stunner. However, this was true for only 0.01% of birds on the Italian farms.
de Jong, Ingrid, and Andrew Butterworth. “Part I Synthesis of the Farm Assessments in the UK, Italy and Netherlands.” The Assessment of Animal Welfare on Broiler Farms, edited by Bettina B. Bock and Ingrid de Jong, Welfare Quality Reports No. 18, May 2010.
- ^
Poultry are excluded from the Humane Methods of Slaughter Act, and are instead covered by the Poultry Products Inspection Act. According to a notice by the US Food Safety and Inspection Service:
Although there is no specific federal humane handling and slaughter statute for poultry, under the PPIA, poultry products are more likely to be adulterated if, among other circumstances, they are produced from birds that have not been treated humanely, because such birds are more likely to be bruised or to die other than by slaughter.
Pre-slaughter stunning is rare in countries across Asia (Sinclair et al., 2019).
Sinclair, Michelle, et al. “Livestock Stakeholder Willingness to Embrace Preslaughter Stunning in Key Asian Countries.” Animals, vol. 9, no. 5, 8 May 2019, p. 224, https://doi.org/10.3390/ani9050224.
- ^
This has been widely studied. For example, Gentle et al., 2023, found:
Shackling of commercial poultry involves the insertion of each leg into parallel metal slots and holding the bird inverted for a period of time before stunning and slaughter. Nociceptors signalling noxious stimulation of the skin have been identified in the beak and feathered skin but not in the scaly skin of the leg… The electrical activity was recorded from single C-fibres dissected from the parafibular nerve in anaesthetized animals… After comparing these threshold measurements and the stimulus response data with previous measurements of the force applied to the legs during shackling, it was concluded that shackling is likely to be a very painful procedure.
For more on shackling, see part III.1 of Negro-Calduch et al., 2022, which also provides much more detail on the welfare implications of broiler slaughter more broadly.
Gentle, M J, and V L Tilston. “Nociceptors in the Legs of Poultry: Implications for Potential Pain in Pre-Slaughter Shackling.” Animal Welfare, vol. 9, no. 3, Aug. 2000, pp. 227–236, https://doi.org/10.1017/s0962728600022715.
Negro-Calduch, Elsa, et al. “Quantitative assessment of the welfare impacts of methods for the commercial slaughter of broilers.” Quantifying Pain in Broiler Chickens: Impact of the Better Chicken Commitment and Adoption of Slower-Growing Breeds on Broiler Welfare, edited by Cynthia Schuck-Paim and Wladimir J. Alonso, Welfare Footprint Project, 1 May 2022. (Read the chapter as a google doc).
- ^
After assessing 10 Dutch farms and 10 Italian farms, de Jong et al., 2010, found that 7.1% of birds in the Dutch farms were not adequately stunned when exiting the stunner. However, this was true for only 0.01% of birds on the Italian farms.
de Jong, Ingrid, and Andrew Butterworth. “Part I Synthesis of the Farm Assessments in the UK, Italy and Netherlands.” The Assessment of Animal Welfare on Broiler Farms, edited by Bettina B. Bock and Ingrid de Jong, Welfare Quality Reports No. 18, May 2010.
- ^
The 2021 US United Egg Producers guidelines say:
Space allowance should be in the range of 67 to 86 square inches of usable space per bird to optimize hen welfare.
That’s 0.04m2 to 0.05m2.
In the EU, battery cages are banned, but the majority of laying hens are still housed in ‘enriched cages’ which are required to be at least 0.075m2, according to Council Directive 1999/74/EC.
The welfare implications of this lack of space are set out in Schuck-Paim et al., 2021.
Schuck-Paim, Cynthia, and Wladimir J. Alonso. “The Burden of Psychological Pain in Laying Hens: Behavioral Deprivation.” Quantifying Pain in Laying Hens: A Blueprint for the Comparative Analysis of Welfare in Animals, edited by Cynthia Schuck-Paim and Wladimir J Alonso, Welfare Footprint Project, 2 Aug. 2021.
- ^
Laying hens are highly susceptible to osteoporosis (Whitehead et al., 2000) which can lead to spontaneous bone fractures, especially of the keel bone. According to Toscano et al., 2020:
The [keel bone fracture] issue has also been cited as a major problem by the European Food Safety Authority Panel on Animal Health and Welfare (Welfare. 2015) and a North American–based consortium of welfare researchers (Lay et al., 2011)…
The number of affected birds within commercial flocks can range between 20 and 96%, based on reports from various countries including Belgium (Heerkens et al., 2015), Canada (Petrik et al., 2015), Denmark (Riber and Hinrichsen, 2016), The Netherlands (Rodenburg et al., 2008), Switzerland (Kappeli et al., 2011; Stratmann et al., 2015b,a), and the United Kingdom.
Whitehead, C.C., and R.H. Fleming. “Osteoporosis in Cage Layers.” Poultry Science, vol. 79, no. 7, July 2000, pp. 1033–1041, https://doi.org/10.1093/ps/79.7.1033.
Toscano, Michael J., et al. “Explanations for Keel Bone Fractures in Laying Hens: Are There Explanations in Addition to Elevated Egg Production?” Poultry Science, vol. 99, no. 9, 1 Sept. 2020, pp. 4183–4194, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.psj.2020.05.035.
- ^
According to the 2022 Overview Report on the Protection of the Welfare of Laying Hens at All Stages of Production by the European Commission:
Forced moulting is implicitly banned in the EU through Directive 98/58/EC requirements, as it involves long periods of darkness and severe feed restriction.
In the US, there is no legislation, but the United Egg Producers guidelines say “only non-feed withdrawal molt methods will be permitted after January 1, 2006.”
Feed-withdrawal moulting is still standard practice in other regions (Lei et al., 2023):
At present, most laying-hen facilities in China use the fasting method, but with international emphasis on animal welfare, scholars have begun to find ways to improve production efficiency while ensuring animal welfare standards are adhered to.
Lei, Meng, et al. “Effects of Non-Fasting Molting on Performance, Oxidative Stress, Intestinal Morphology, and Liver Health of Laying Hens.” Frontiers in Veterinary Science, vol. 10, 28 Feb. 2023, https://doi.org/10.3389/fvets.2023.1100152.
- ^
Schuck-Paim et al., 2021, survey the literature on the frequency of egg peritonitis:
[Egg peritonitis] has been shown to be the main cause of mortality in commercial layers by various studies… For example, in a flock of Babcock White Leghorns kept in single-tier aviaries in Canada, egg yolk peritonitis accounted for 22% of all deaths over a period of 33 weeks [70]. In another study conducted with 1,800,000 hens in conventional cages, and 118,000 hens in furnished cages, the proportion of deaths attributed to egg yolk peritonitis, salpingitis, internal layer and egg bound was respectively 26.6%, 4.7%, 1.4% and 0.7%, totalling 33% of mortality, by far the most prevalent cause of death [60]. Similarly, in the only study that compared the causes of normal layer mortality across housing systems using standardized diagnostic definitions, egg yolk peritonitis (defined by the authors as the congestion of visceral vessels with the presence of egg yolk within the coelomic cavity) was diagnosed as the cause of death in 25%, 19% and 12% of the daily mortalities in conventional cages, furnished cages and multi-tier aviaries, respectively, with salpingitis (oviduct greatly distended with a fetid yellow, easily crumbled exudate) responsible for an extra 2%, 1.6% and 3% of the deaths, and internal layer/egg bound for 0.5%, 0.3% and 1.2%, respectively [63]. Thus, EGPS (which includes both conditions) accounted for 27.6%, 21% and 16.5% of the mortality in conventional cages, furnished cages and multi-tier aviaries, respectively.
Studies on the prevalence of non-fatal cases of EGPS are even more scarce, with only one investigation published since 2000 [73]. The study, which involved the culling of a random sample of seemingly healthy hens from 15 Danish flocks at the end of the laying period reported that 4.13% of hens in furnished cages and 5.57% in single-tier aviaries had infections in the reproductive tract (salpingitis, peritonitis and oophoritis combined) or chronic lesions (e.g. scarification and/or serosal fibrosis on abdominal organs), the non-fatal chronic form of EGPS (Figure 5.2 in the Chapter 5 [5]).
For an analysis of the welfare implications of egg peritonitis, see Negro-Calduch et al., 2021.
Schuck-Paim, Cynthia, and Wladimir J. Alonso. “The Prevalence of Welfare Challenges Affecting Laying Hens in Different Housing Systems.” Quantifying Pain in Laying Hens: A Blueprint for the Comparative Analysis of Welfare in Animals, edited by Cynthia Schuck-Paim and Wladimir J Alonso, Welfare Footprint Project, 2 Aug. 2021
Negro-Calduch, et al. “Egg Peritonitis Syndrome: A Painful and Prevalent Disease in Commercial Layers.” Quantifying Pain in Laying Hens: A Blueprint for the Comparative Analysis of Welfare in Animals, edited by Cynthia Schuck-Paim and Wladimir J Alonso, Welfare Footprint Project, 2 Aug. 2021
- ^
A report by the Council for Agricultural Science and Technology reported that about 30% of cage-free hens in the US had outdoor access in 2018 (Jacob et al., 2018):
According to the USDA–AMS June 4, 2018, cage-free shell egg report (USDA–AMS 2018), there were almost 54 million cage-free egg layers in the United States during the month of May 2018. This represents 14% of all the table egg layers in the country (USDA–NASS 2018). This would include both confined and free-range production systems. Of the cage-free hens, almost 16 million were certified organic, which would have access to the outdoors. This would represent only 0.3% of the total hen inventory for May.
In the EU, all free-range hens are required daily access to outdoor space, while ‘organic’ hens are only required outdoor access for one third of their life see section 6 of the 2022 Overview Report on the Protection of the Welfare of Laying Hens at All Stages of Production by the European Commission.
But access to outdoor space doesn’t mean the hens actually go outside — only that they have a route to do so. According to Larsen et al., 2017:
In this exploratory study, we tracked free-range laying hens on two commercial flocks with Radio Frequency Identification (RFID) technology with the aim to examine individual hen variation in range use… Most of the hens in both flocks (68.6% in Flock A, and 82.2% in Flock B) accessed the range every day during the study.
Pettersson et al., 2019, found that:
There are many studies that have reported figures for range use in free-range hens, although these figures are often lower than consumer expectation, rarely exceeding 40%. Less information is available on range use by individual hens, particularly in large commercial systems… Many factors affecting percentage range use have been identified, often through observational studies of commercial flocks, particularly the effects of climate, shelter and flock size. However, certain factors are somewhat underrepresented in the literature. The effect of pophole size and elevation is little studied, likely because of the difficulty in manipulating this factor. Similarly, little research has examined external stocking density or space requirements on the range.
Jacob, Jacqueline P. , et al. Impact of Free-Range Poultry Production Systems on Animal Health, Human Health, Productivity, Environment, Food Safety, and Animal Welfare Issues. CAST. Issue Paper 61, July 2018.
Larsen, Hannah, et al. “Individual Ranging Behaviour Patterns in Commercial Free-Range Layers as Observed through RFID Tracking.” Animals, vol. 7, no. 12, 9 Mar. 2017, p. 21, https://doi.org/10.3390/ani7030021.
- ^
A systematic review of keel bone fracture rates across housing conditions (Rufener et al., 2020) found similar rates of prevalence across caged and cage-free housing systems (see table 1).
Rufener, Christina, and Maja M Makagon. “Keel Bone Fractures in Laying Hens: A Systematic Review of Prevalence across Age, Housing Systems, and Strains.” Journal of Animal Science, vol. 98, no. Supplement_1, Aug. 2020, pp. S36–S51, https://doi.org/10.1093/jas/skaa145.
- ^
Shuck-Paim et al., 2021a, conduct an analysis of the literature looking at the prevalence of injurious pecking in various systems. They conclude:
Thus, to make a first attempt at estimating the burden of pain endured by laying hens as a result of skin wounds we provisorily consider the prevalence ranges reported in this section (5-15% in conventional cages, 1 to 10% in furnished cages and 5 to 30% in cage-free aviaries). For vent wounds, the only study found was conducted in 2006, hence to the reported prevalence we add uncertainty intervals (3-8%, 1-4% and 5-15% in conventional cages, furnished cages and aviaries, respectively)…
0-0.16%, 0.03-0.24% and 0.15-0.8% of all birds in conventional cages, furnished cages and cage-free aviaries [are] likely to die from a cannibalistic attack if cumulative mortality ranges from 3 to 8%. Of these deaths, 60-90% are estimated to result from fatal vent pecking events, and the remaining from fatal cannibalistic attacks.An account of the welfare implications of injurious pecking can be found in Schuck-Paim et al., 2021b.
Schuck-Paim, Cynthia, and Wladimir J. Alonso. “The Prevalence of Welfare Challenges Affecting Laying Hens in Different Housing Systems.” Quantifying Pain in Laying Hens: A Blueprint for the Comparative Analysis of Welfare in Animals, edited by Cynthia Schuck-Paim and Wladimir J Alonso, Welfare Footprint Project, 2 Aug. 2021
Schuck-Paim, Cynthia, et al. “Welfare Implications of Injurious Pecking in Laying Hens.” Quantifying Pain in Laying Hens: A Blueprint for the Comparative Analysis of Welfare in Animals, edited by Cynthia Schuck-Paim and Wladimir J Alonso, Welfare Footprint Project, 2 Aug. 2021
- ^
We couldn’t find good data on the prevalence of beak trimming. According to an article in Canadian Poultry Magazine, although some member states of the EU have banned beak trimming, 80% of hens in Europe are still beak-trimmed as of April 2019. Beak trimming is allowed and likely common in the majority of countries including the UK, most of Australia, the US, and China.
Beak trimming is restricted in some organic standards
The US Department of Agriculture Laying Hen Welfare Fact Sheet (2010) discusses the negative effects of beak trimming on welfare:
Following beak trimming, several anatomical, physiological, and biochemical changes occur in cut peripheral nerves and damaged tissues. There is a considerable body of morphological, neurophysiological, behavioral and production research demonstrating the emergence of several markers of acute and chronic pain (e.g., persistent lethargy and guarding behaviors, reduced feed intake, and development of neuromas) as a result of trimming. This is of more concern when the beak trimming is conducted in birds which are 5 weeks old or older using a hotblade beak trimmer.
- ^
Egg-laying hens are depopulated at around 1.5 to 2 years of age, according to industry sources. That means, if there are around 7–10 billion egg-laying hens alive at any one time, we’re breeding around 3.5–7 billion hens a year. For every female egg-laying hen born, there’s on average one male chick born since half of all chicks born are male. As a result, we cull around 3.5–7 billion male chicks every year.
In the EU and US, the approved methods for male-chick culling are maceration and gassing. Maceration is meant to be an instantaneous death, but according to a report for the European Parliament:
A 2019 study by the European Food Safety Authority (EFSA) found, however, that maceration may fail to protect the welfare of such animals. More specifically, EFSA identified certain risks to the protection of welfare during the maceration of chicks: slow rotation of blades or rollers, overloading of machinery, and rollers set too wide. This can result in failure to kill the chicks, leaving them conscious, and in pain, distress and fear.
While in-ovo sexing technologies are now available, a 2023 report by Innovate Animal Ag found that only 15% of male chicks were identified in-ovo in the EU, and the technology has not gained any traction in the US.
- ^
The issues at slaughter are similar to those for broiler hens. For details, see Schuck-Paim et al., 2021.
Schuck-Paim, Cynthia, et al. “The Last Day of a Hen’s Life: Depopulation and Transport.” Quantifying Pain in Laying Hens: A Blueprint for the Comparative Analysis of Welfare in Animals, edited by Cynthia Schuck-Paim and Wladimir J Alonso, Welfare Footprint Project, 2 Aug. 2021
- ^
Finding reliable sources on the prevalence of different stocking densities globally is challenging. To be conservative, we will focus on what is known about EU housing conditions of pigs.
The European Food Safety Authority reports that (Nierlsen et al., 2022):
Indoor group systems for pregnant sows and gilts represent the main housing system in the EU since 2013 (Commission Regulation (EC) 889/2008).
The keeping of gilts and dry sows in housing which combines an indoor area and an outdoor concrete area is seen mainly in small-scale traditional farms or in farms certified for organic production in many European countries (Fr ¨uh et al., 2013). The proportion of sows in the EU which are kept in this system is consequently small… The group size and space allowance can vary widely, although if on a certified organic farm, the pen must provide a minimum space per pig of 2.5 m 2 indoors plus 1.9 m 2 outdoors (Commission Regulation (EC) 889/2008).
In most European countries [the outdoor paddock] system is used to a very limited extent, mainly on farms which are certified for organic production (Fr ¨uh et al., 2013) or other niche label schemes. However, there are notable exceptions where large commercial herds for conventional production house their breeding sows in outdoor paddocks, as is the case for 40% of sows in the UK and a smaller number of herds in France and other countries in regions with suitable climate and soil type (Edwards, 1994). The animals are typically enclosed by electrified fences and provided with bedded wooden or metal shelters. The group size and space allowance within a paddock are highly variable, depending on farm size and soil type.
Based on this, we think it is reasonable to conclude that the vast majority of pigs are kept indoors without access to the outdoors.
The EU pig protection policy stipulates:
Standards concerning floor area are set according to the weight of the animal: between 0.15 m2 for pigs weighing less than 10 kg and 1.0 m2 per animal over 110 kg; 1.64 m2 per gilt; 2.25 m2 per sow; 6 m2 for a boar (10 m2 if the boar is used for natural services).
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose, et al. “Welfare of Pigs on Farm.” EFSA Journal, vol. 20, no. 8, Aug. 2022, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2022.7421.
- ^
A report from the EU Reference Centre for Animal Welfare Pigs — aiming to support welfare inspectors assessing heat stress in pigs — describes the current EU policies on temperature:
There are hardly climatic legal requirements for pigs in the EU-regulations. However, on a national level rules can be stricter, but often formulated as “open norms”. Directive 98/58/EC states that the accommodation should “not be harmful” to the pigs, which can only be checked by animal based indicators given in section 4.2. However, legal limits are not available in most countries, with difficult enforcement as a consequence.
COUNCIL DIRECTIVE 2008/120/EC 3 (EU, 2008) Annex I, Chapter I, Article 3: The accommodation for pigs must be constructed in such a way as to allow the animals to: have access to a lying area physically and thermally comfortable as well as adequately drained and clean which allows all the animals to lie at the same time. Directive 98/58/EC (EU, 1998) Annex: Buildings and accommodation Article 10: Air circulation, dust levels, temperature, relative air humidity and gas concentrations must be kept within limits which are not harmful to the animals.”
The European Food Safety Authority report on the welfare of pigs on farms (Nielsen et al., 2022) identified heat stress as a pertinent welfare concern, particularly in modern agriculture and for sows in farrowing crates:
Selection for fast growth rates and larger more prolific sows makes modern pigs more sensitive to heat stress… ‘Heat stress’ was classified as highly relevant in sows housed in farrowing crates.
Temperatures above 25 degrees celsius were identified as the upper limit of the acceptable range for heat in farrowing and lactating sows:
Quiniou and Noblet (1999) investigated the influence of high ambient temperature on performance of lactating sows. Comparing five ambient temperatures (18, 22, 25, 27 and 29°C) maintained constant over the 21-day lactation period, they found that skin temperature increased with increased ambient temperature (34.6–37.4°C between 18°C and 29°C), whereas udder temperature reached a plateau at 25°C (38.3°C). Moreover, the respiratory rate increased from 26 to 124 breaths/min between 18°C and 29°C, indicating that the evaporative critical temperature, corresponding to the upper limit of the comfort zone was below 22°C. They thus concluded that temperatures above 25°C seem to be upper critical temperature for lactating sows.
Ambient summer temperatures are likely to exceed this range often, leading to even higher temperatures in indoor housing. A review of the effects of heat stress on meat quality indicates that heat stress is a common and substantial cause of reduced pork production (Gonzalez-Rivas et al., 2019):
More recently, and despite heat stress abatement strategies, the annual economic losses to the US swine industry during the summer months were estimated to be $900 million (Pollmann, 2010). Unfortunately, the harmful consequences of heat stress to animal health and production are likely to continue in the future, particularly if selection for improved production traits is prioritised against thermotolerance and climate adaptation.
Potentially due to the lack of specific regulatory requirements, it is difficult to find exact estimates of the proportion of pigs that are experiencing heat stress. One industry publication, Agrifuture Magazine (an outlet from the German Agricultural Society), presents data suggesting that the sows in farrowing crates from sampled farms experienced ambient temperatures about 25 degrees celsius ranging from 34–91% of the time during summer months in 2017.
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose, et al. “Welfare of Pigs on Farm.” EFSA Journal, vol. 20, no. 8, Aug. 2022, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2022.7421.
Gonzalez-Rivas, Paula A., et al. “Effects of Heat Stress on Animal Physiology, Metabolism, and Meat Quality: A Review.” Meat Science, vol. 162, Apr. 2020, p. 108025, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.meatsci.2019.108025.
- ^
The EU policy for the protection of pigs (Directive 2008/120/EC — minimum standards for the protection of pigs) allows for tooth clipping without any form of analgesia (see section ‘Painful operations on animals’). As a result, we think it’s likely that this is common globally.
The European Food Safety Authority report on the welfare of pigs on farms (Nielsen et al., 2022) identified tooth clipping as a welfare concern in Europe, highlighting both the painful experience, lack of analgesics, and poor acute and long-term outcomes for the majority of piglets:
Epidemiological data are scarce. However, there is considerable anecdoctal evidence indicating that tooth reduction is a frequent practice on EU farms (Chou et al., 2020a). It appears that shortening of suckling piglets’ teeth within the first day(s) of life is carried out in many countries worldwide (e.g. Fredriksen et al., 2009), and there is little reason to believe that this has recently changed (Prunier et al., 2020a).
…Tooth reduction is commonly carried out in the first days of life (Prunier et al., 2021). The procedure involves the shortening of the upper and lower third incisor and the canines (total of 8 teeth) to remove the sharp part of the teeth without opening of the dental pulp. However, as teeth can have different length this can easily go wrong. A maximum removal of the top third of each tooth is generally recommended, but in practice this varies considerably, from a small fraction to the whole tooth above the gum line being removed (Gallois et al., 2005; Fu et al., 2019).>
Traditionally, either manual clipping (performed using side‐cutting pliers, called ‘clippers’) or electronic grinders (tooth abrasion with a stone) are used. Data of the actual distribution of both practices are missing.…The practices of grinding and clipping cause also acute pain and long‐term pain. Acute pain is associated with the short‐term effect of the procedure of teeth reduction, while long‐term pain is caused by subsequent inflammatory processes of the tissues involved.
The report concludes that:
- Tooth reduction is a stressful procedure that if performed incorrectly causes short‐ and long‐term pain. In particular, clipping is inherently injurious.
- Grinding to only blunt the sharp tip of the tooth does not injure sensitive tissue when correctly performed.
- Risk mitigation measures to reduce the necessity for teeth reduction include sow management measures to promote optimal milk supply, and balancing the number of piglets with the number of teats.
- In individual litter situations where tooth reduction can be justified, the most effective measure to prevent and mitigate welfare consequences is training of staff in correct procedures.
- Although current legislation highlights teat damage as evidence to justify tooth reduction, facial damage to litter mates is a more related animal‐based measure.
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose, et al. “Welfare of Pigs on Farm.” EFSA Journal, vol. 20, no. 8, Aug. 2022, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2022.7421.
- ^
The EU animal welfare policy on the protection of pigs allows for tail-docking prior to the seventh day of life without any form of analgesia (see section “Painful operations on animals”). As a result, we think it’s likely that this is common globally.
The European Food and Authority report on the welfare of pigs on farms (Nielsen et al., 2022) identifies tail docking as a leading welfare concern in farmed pigs in Europe, summarising the evidence:
Tail docking is widely performed to reduce tail biting lesions in pigs raised under intensive conditions (De Briyne et al., 2018). However, while many evidence suggested that tail docking reduces the risk of tail biting lesions, other studies indicate this will not eliminate tail lesion totally (D’Eath et al., 2016; Lahrmann et al., 2017; Thodberg et al., 2018, reviewed by Prunier et al., 2020b). Tail docking causes acute and medium‐term pain in the pigs (see Section 6.3.2). Routine tail docking is therefore a systematic source of pain that affects all the reared pigs (Valros and Heinonen, 2015).
They conclude:
- Welfare consequences of tail‐docking in piglets will include soft tissue lesions and integument damage, bone lesion and handling stress, causing the overarching welfare consequences of pain and fear.
- Whilst tail docking is effective in reducing the risk of tail lesions, it is not necessary if husbandry practices and management are appropriate.
- Tail docking is painful, with short and medium‐term negative welfare consequences including soft tissue lesions and integument damage, bone lesions (including fractures of the spinal vertebrae), handling stress, fear and pain.
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose, et al. “Welfare of Pigs on Farm.” EFSA Journal, vol. 20, no. 8, Aug. 2022, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2022.7421
- ^
The EU animal welfare policy on the protection of pigs allows for the castration of pigs prior to the seventh day of life without any form of analgesia.
The European Food and Authority report on the welfare of pigs on farms (Nielsen et al., 2022) identifies castration as a leading welfare concern in farmed pigs in Europe, summarising the practice and prevalence:Castration is a traditional practice in many countries and is still practiced in the majority of EU pig farms. It aims at reducing aggressive and sexual behaviour in adult male pigs and avoiding boar taint (an offensive odour resulting from androstenone, skatole and indol compounds) in pork and pork products. On farm, the procedure usually involves rapidly cutting the skin (using a scalpel) and the spermatic cords (using a scalpel or an instrument called ’emasculator’ which cuts and squeezes the spermatic cord) without administration of anaesthesia nor analgesia in piglets under 7 days (here considered the ‘surgical castration’ method). Castration by tearing the spermatic chords, even if not allowed in Europe, is still being performed in some cases (Schmid et al., 2021).
A recent scientific review on invasive procedures in piglets summarised the negative implications of this practice to piglet welfare, confirming that there is now neural (observed via brain electric activity), hormonal, metabolic and behavioural evidence of pain that can last well after the procedure (Prunier et al., 2021)…neural pain pathways in pigs and humans are very similar and that a strong homology between porcine and human nociceptive neuron exist (Prunier et al., 2021), suggesting that castration can result in severe pain to piglets. These results align with previous studies reporting pain in piglets during (Taylor and Weary, 2000; Taylor et al., 2001; Kluivers‐Poodt et al., 2012; Viscardi and Turner, 2018) and after the castration procedure (Prunier et al., 2006; Kluivers‐Poodt et al., 2007).
It was estimated that only 5% of piglets received analgesia and anaesthesia and ~ 40% received analgesia (alone) in 18 countries during castration.
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose, et al. “Welfare of Pigs on Farm.” EFSA Journal, vol. 20, no. 8, Aug. 2022, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2022.7421.
- ^
The EU animal welfare policy on the protection of pigs allows for the nose-ringing of pigs kept in outdoor husbandry systems, but some member states have banned the practice (e.g. the Netherlands, Austria, Sweden and Denmark). The EU tends to have higher animal welfare standards than other countries.
The EU Reference Centre for Animal Welfare Pigs, in response to a question about the effect of rooting on welfare, reported:Pigs are highly motivated for rooting and other explorative behaviours to investigate their environment, to forage or to prepare a place to lie (Studnitz et al, 2007). In natural environments, sows spend about 30% of their waking hours rooting and about the same amount grazing (Stolba and Wood-Gush, 1989). Rydhmer and Canario (2013) confirm this and state that “on pasture, feed-related behaviors like rooting, grazing, and exploring substrate account for 75% of daily activity”. When sows are kept outdoors, the rooting behaviour may lead to removal of large parts of the grass cover, potentially resulting in minerals leaching to the ground water and leaving less plants for grazing. Nose ringing reduces or eliminates this behaviour, as rooting probably becomes painful.
…The rooting disc is very sensitive and innervated by a high density of sensory nerves. Although not quantifiable in any way, the application of rings by perforating the tissue, the healing of the wound and the use of the nose after ringing are likely to be painful. The use of anaesthesia during application is not common. Some cases of inflammation are reported. The aim of the ring is to make the use of the nose for deep rooting painful, or at least very uncomfortable. Studnitz et al. (2007) report that the total amount of exploratory behaviour (rooting, manipulating, sniffing and chewing) was not significantly affected by ringing, but rings prevented sows from rooting and increased chewing and manipulation behaviour in comparison to not ringed sows. They did not see signs of rebound in rooting motivation after ring removal.
- ^
In response to a resolution from the American Veterinary Medical Association, Trace et a., 2005, conducted a review into housing for pregnant shows.
They found that gestation crates have severe welfare implications – although noted a few ways in which they are better than commonly-used group housing:
Most research to date indicates that generally accepted physiologic measures of stress are
similar for sows housed in individual gestation stalls and in group pens. On the basis of information available at this time, Task Force members considered it reasonable to conclude that stall housing is not more physiologically stressful to sows than group housing.…Gestation stalls, particularly when used in conjunction with feed restriction, may adversely affect welfare by restricting behavior, including foraging, movement, and postural changes. Stereotypies related to behavioral restriction can be reduced by providing bedding, foraging material, roughage, or a combination of these. Simply providing space to turn around is unlikely to resolve these repetitive, non–purpose-directed behavior patterns.
…Other factors contributing to poor welfare in stalls and small, unbedded pens include lack of exercise, lack of environmental complexity, lack of rooting/chewing materials, and an inability for the sow to exert control over her environment.
…Aggression has been reported in all types of housing systems, but it is most often worse and sometimes severe in group housing. Vulva biting, one of the most common and serious aggressive interactions, most often occurs in group pens that do not allow for simultaneous feeding of sows (eg, those using electronic sow feeders).
…Injury rate is lower for sows housed in gestation stalls, compared with sows housed in groups.
The use of gestation crates varies around the world. There are bans in some US states (the US produces around 11% of the world’s pork). According to a 2022 report from the USDA:
Over the past two decades, multiple States have passed animal welfare regulations in hog production. These regulations ban the common practice of using gestation crates—metal enclosures used to house pregnant sows—or stipulate space requirements for animals to stand and turn around. In addition to restrictions during production, two of these States, California and Massachusetts, passed retail sales restrictions that prohibit the sale of pork originating from animals kept in gestation-crate systems or their direct offspring. Hog welfare regulations are concentrated in States with relatively small pork industries. The proportion of the national herd covered by gestation crate bans is currently estimated at 3 percent based on expected production in 2022. Except for Michigan, each State with existing bans on gestation crates has produced, on average, less than 1 percent of total U.S. pork production (in pounds) since 2018. Ohio will become the largest hog-producing State to ban gestation crates when its regulations go into effect in 2026. Based on State hog inventories in December 2020, projected coverage of the total U.S. hog herd and the breeding herd is expected to remain below 10 percent of hogs and pigs under current State regulations through 2026.”
The US situation may be a bit better than this picture paints though due to corporate policy initiatives and California prop 12 (implemented in 2024) which prohibits the use of gestation crates for more than 24 hours in a 30 day period and no more than 6 hours in a 24 hour period for all pork products sold in the state regardless of the origin of the product.
In the EU (which produces 18% of the world’s pork), the use of gestation crates is restricted but not banned:
Individual housing in stalls Under EU legislation, gilts and sows can be kept in this system only for a limited period of time, i.e. gilts from service up to maximum 4 weeks after service, and sows from weaning up to maximum 4 weeks after service.
Individual or gestation stalls are the main housing system for pregnant sows and gilts from service up to farrowing worldwide (Ryan et al., 2015). In the EU, they are not permitted for use beyond 28 days post-service (Commission Regulation (EC) 889/200820 ). Some MSs have stricter legislative restrictions on their use. For example, in the Netherlands, gilts and dry sows can only be held in stalls for a maximum of 4 days post-service, in Austria for a maximum of 10 days and Sweden not at all except for the actual insemination. In Denmark, in 2020 legislation has been passed that sows housed in buildings built after2015 must be loose housed from weaning to farrowing; from 2035 this requirement applies to all sows.Similarly, Germany passed a legislation in 2020 introducing a ban on sow stalls, but it will not become mandatory until 2030.
Here, ‘service’ refers to mating.
The Welfare of Farmed Animals (England) Regulations 2000 , The Welfare of Farmed Animals (Scotland) Regulations 2000, The Welfare of Farmed Animals Regulations (Northern Ireland) 2000 and The [The Welfare of Farmed Animals (Wales) Regulations 2001] collectively ban gestation crates cross the entire UK:
A pig shall be free to turn round without difficulty at all times. The accommodation used for pigs shall be constructed in such a way as to allow each pig to stand up, lie down and rest without difficulty; have a clean place in which it can rest; and see other pigs, unless the pig is isolated for veterinary reasons. The dimension of any stall or pen [NI: used for holding individual pigs in accordance with these Regulations] shall be such that the internal area is not less than the square of the length of the pig, and no internal side is less than 75% of the length of the pig, the length of the pig in each case being measured from the tip of its snout to the base of its tail while it is standing with its back straight.
It’s worth remembering that, as we noted earlier, compliance rates in the EU range from around 90% to around 20%, depending on the regulation (and way in which compliance rates are estimated). We’d guess there are similar rates of noncompliance elsewhere, e.g. in the US and UK.
In China (responsible for 50% of the world’s pork production), there are no specific policies defining the housing requirements for the welfare of pigs.
A 2008 study of farming practices suggests the the use of gestation crates is likely widespread in China (Li, 2008):
Gestation and farrowing crates are the most popular farming tool of Western invention. We noticed them in all 9 breeding farms. Two of these farms were in inland Jiangxi and Anhui. Their wide use across the country is therefore no exaggeration. Sow crates are popular because they ensure success of pregnancy and prevent breeding sows from crashing the piglets. Productivity and efficiency are the attractions. No farm workers and owners appeared to know that use of farrowing crates is to be phased out in European Union nations. According to the manager of a Liaoning breeding farm, his sows were generally confined up to 150 days in standard crates. All the interviewees of the breeding farms referred to such modern farming practice glowingly.”
However, more recently, specific Chinese pork producers (e.g. Quinglian Food Company, Da Bei Nong, and more) have made pledges to move away from gestation crates voluntarily to improve welfare standards. That said, we’re unsure how many sows are covered by voluntary pledges, and there’s no enforcement, so we’d guess the vast majority of sows in China are still kept in gestation crates.
Li, Peter J. “Exponential Growth, Animal Welfare, Environmental and Food Safety Impact: The Case of China’s Livestock Production.” Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, vol. 22, no. 3, 30 Dec. 2008, pp. 217–240, https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-008-9140-7.
Rhodes, R. Tracy, et al. “A Comprehensive Review of Housing for Pregnant Sows.” Journal of the American Veterinary Medical Association, vol. 227, no. 10, Nov. 2005, pp. 1580–90, https://doi.org/10.2460/javma.2005.227.1580.
- ^
The EU animal welfare policy on the protection of pigs allows farrowing crates.
The European Food Safety Authority identified individual farrowing crates as a main welfare concern of lactating sows (Nielsen et al., 2022). They summarise the overall situation:
Individual crates are the main housing system for farrowing and lactating sows. The sows are normally moved to the farrowing crates in the week before expected time of farrowing and removed after the weaning of the piglets. A farrowing crate consists of metal bars running along the length of the sow. Sometimes, additional metal bars are placed on the top of the cage to prevent the sow from jumping or climbing in the attempt to escape. The length of the crate is about 2 m with a width between 0.45 and 0.65 m. To allow assisted farrowing, an unobstructed area behind the sow or gilt must be present. The space provided in the crates allows the sow to stand up and lie down, but not turn around or walk.Nowadays, sows are substantially larger than 40 years ago (Moustsen et al., 2011; Nielsen et al., 2018) and they rear a larger litter for a longer lactation length than before. Therefore, physical and behavioural restriction have increased over this period, especially in crates which cannot be adapted to the length and width of the sows.
Farrowing crates were introduced with the aim to prevent crushing piglets by the sow and thus reduce piglet mortality (Edwards, 2002). However, aggressive behaviour towards the piglets has been shown to increase when the sows are crated as compared to sows in loose housing system (Jarvis et al., 2006). Sows in crated system showed also higher restlessness, which further increases the risk of overlying when the piglets try to access the udder (Ocepek and Andersen, 2017).
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose, et al. “Welfare of Pigs on Farm.” EFSA Journal, vol. 20, no. 8, Aug. 2022, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2022.7421.
- ^
The European Food Safety Authority report into pig welfare on farms (Nielsen et al., 2022) identified early weaning age as a welfare concern of piglets. In summary:
Under (semi‐) natural conditions, weaning is a gradual process involving changes in the pattern of nursing which begin from the first week of life and are completed by 13–17 weeks of age (see Section 3.2.5.1). In current farm conditions, piglets are typically weaned abruptly by removal from the sow at a much younger age than 13–17 weeks. A number of different welfare consequences result from this weaning practice because of the psychological stressors involved and the immaturity of the behavioural, digestive and immune system of the piglet at this time (Edwards et al., 2020).
- Abrupt weaning results in a range of welfare consequences including separation stress, prolonged hunger, prolonged thirst, gastro‐intestinal disorders, and inability to perform sucking behaviour, which has further detrimental consequences for resting problems, group stress and soft tissue lesions and integument damage.
- Weaning age has not been associated directly with tail biting, although there may be indirect effects via other welfare consequences (e.g. health‐related) of a poor weaning transition.
- These welfare consequences increase exponentially with reducing weaning age and are particularly pronounced at weaning ages of less than 21 days and with artificial rearing systems. However, there is great variability between different studies and housing systems.
- The welfare benefits of increasing weaning age over the range between 21 and 28 days do appear to be meaningful as a result of the increasing maturity of behavioural, digestive and immunological systems over this period.
- There are inadequate data to assess the welfare consequences of weaning ages greater than 28 days but indications from the ABMs that have been investigated are that, under good management, any welfare benefits are less pronounced.
The report also describes standard practice for inseminating sows after the weaning:
Sows are typically served at their first standing heat post‐weaning. Service is either natural (by the boar) or by artificial insemination (AI).
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose, et al. “Welfare of Pigs on Farm.” EFSA Journal, vol. 20, no. 8, Aug. 2022, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2022.7421.
- ^
In the EU, pigs must be stunned prior to slaughter in accordance with mandatory stunning as set out by Article 4.4 of the Council Regulation 1099/2009, with the exception of animals subject to particular methods of slaughter prescribed by religious rites.
The European Food Safety Authority report on welfare of pigs at slaughter (Nielsen et al., 2020) indicates that electrical (i.e. electronarcosis) and controlled atmosphere (carbon dioxide) stunning are the most common at large slaughterhouses:
The stunning methods that have been identified as relevant for pigs can be grouped in three categories: (1) electrical, (2) controlled atmospheres and (3) mechanical.
Electrical methods include head-only and head-to-body. Controlled atmosphere stunning methods (CAS) include carbon dioxide (CO2) at high concentration (defined in this opinion as higher than 80% by volume), inert gases and CO2 associated with inert gases. The mechanical methods that have been described in this report are captive bolt, percussive blow to the head and firearm with free projectile. These methods are mainly used as backup method or for small-scale slaughtering as in small abattoirs or on-farm slaughter.
During phase 2 [stunning], pigs might experience pain and fear during restraint (in electrical and mechanical methods) and during exposure to CAS before loss of consciousness.
Furthermore, ineffective stunning will lead to persistence of consciousness during hoisting, sticking [throat cut] and bleeding. Recovery of consciousness might occur in effectively stunned animals if sticking was delayed or was not properly done. Both these situations will also cause pain and fear to animals and are considered an important animal welfare concern in the stunning process.
The stunning phase itself causes pain and distress. For example, multiple studies indicate that pigs find carbon dioxide exposure distressing and painful — the European Food Safety Authority report on pig welfare at slaughter concluded:
It has been demonstrated that pigs find CO2 in high concentrations aversive and, given a free choice, they avoid such atmospheres (Raj and Gregory, 1995; EFSA, 2004). CO2 itself causes irritation of the nasal mucosa and exposure is therefore inducing a painful sensation (Steiner et al., 2019). CO2 has the potential to cause welfare consequences via three different mechanisms: (1) pain due to formation of carbonic acid on respiratory and ocular membranes, (2) production of so-called air hunger and a feeling of breathlessness and (3) direct stimulation of ion channels within the amygdala associated with the fear response (Raj, 2006; Beausoleil and Mellor, 2015; AVMA, 2020).
For head-only electrical stunning, the EFSA report concludes pigs experience pain and fear during the restraining phase, and if consciousness is regained:
During the restraining, the welfare consequences are pain and fear. After stunning, if the stunning is ineffective or if the animals recover consciousness, the welfare consequences are pain and fear due to persistence of consciousness. Therefore, consciousness is not a welfare consequence per se but a prerequisite for experiencing pain and fear.
After stunning, pigs are ‘stuck’ (i.e. their throats are cut) and exsanguinated (i.e. bled out until death). Some pigs will be conscious during this phase even when pre-stunned.
A field study of slaughterhouses in Switzerland, Austria, and Germany found high rates of insufficient stunning prior to throat cutting leading to pigs being conscious during the throat cut and bleeding phase of slaughter (von Wenzlawowicz et al., 2022):
The proportions of assessments in which there were no failures were 28% (captive bolt), 12% (electrical stunning; pen), 21% (electrical stunning; trap), 31% (electrical stunning; automatic restrainer) and 13% (controlled atmosphere CO2). The mean percentages of animals showing signs not compatible with sufficient depth of stunning were 13.5 (± 19.0)% (captive bolt), 12.5 (± 16.4)% (electrical stunning; pen), 10.9 (± 11.4)% (electrical stunning; trap), 3.2 (± 3.3)% (electrical stunning; automatic restrainer) and 7.5 (± 13.0)% (controlled atmosphere CO2) showing a high variability between premises assessed.
During the sticking process, some pigs will receive multiple throat cuts due to failure of the first cut, increasing the time between the stunning and death and putting them at higher risk of regaining consciousness (Nielsen et al., 2020):
It is also important to note that effective captive bolt stunning of pigs leads to severe convulsions which may impede prompt and accurate sticking, especially if the pig is not restrained appropriately… Various studies have shown that up to 13% of pigs required more than a single sticking attempt to bleed out properly (Anil et al., 2000; Spencer and Veary, 2010).This hazard can lead to recovery of consciousness. There are no published data concerning this hazard.”
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose, et al. “Welfare of Pigs at Slaughter.” EFSA Journal, vol. 18, no. 6, June 2020, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2020.6148.
von Wenzlawowicz, M, et al. “Identifying Reasons for Stun Failures in Slaughterhouses for Cattle and Pigs: A Field Study.” Animal Welfare, vol. 21, no. 1, 1 June 2012, pp. 51–60, https://doi.org/10.7120/096272812×13353700593527.
- ^
Thompson et al. (2022) describe the state of current guidelines:
The current recommendations for freestall accommodation space allowances for dairy cattle worldwide have no scientific basis and show great variability; for example total space allowance recommendations range from 6.0 to 11 m2 per animal amongst countries worldwide. For context an average adult commercial dairy cow would occupy in the region of 1.8–2 m2 when standing.
In practice, the size of housing space likely differs substantially between farms. Indeed, a field study of dairy cows in the UK by Thompson et al. (2020) found large variability in amounts of total space per cow across randomly selected farms:
Large variability was identified between farms in total space available per cow, with a range from 5.4 to 12.7 m2 [mean = 8.3 m2, median = 8.2 m2, interquartile range (IQR) = 1.9 m2]. The mean living space was 2.5 m2, with a range of 0.5 m2 to 6.4 m2 (median = 2.4 m2, IQR = 1.6 to 3.2 m2).
In a study of dairy farms in Canada, Charlton et al. (2014) found:
On average, stall width was 116 cm (±5.90 cm; range = 104–137 cm) and average stall length was 240 cm (±17.67 cm; range = 207–314 cm).
Thompson, Jake S., et al. “A Randomised Controlled Trial to Evaluate the Impact of Indoor Living Space on Dairy Cow Production, Reproduction and Behaviour.” Scientific Reports, vol. 12, no. 1, Mar. 2022, https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-022-07826-9.
Thompson, J.S., et al. “Field Survey to Evaluate Space Allowances for Dairy Cows in Great Britain.” Journal of Dairy Science, vol. 103, no. 4, Apr. 2020, pp. 3745–3759, https://doi.org/10.3168/jds.2019-17004.
Charlton, G. L., et al. “Stocking Density, Milking Duration, and Lying Times of Lactating Cows on Canadian Freestall Dairy Farms.” Journal of Dairy Science, vol. 97, no. 5, May 2014, pp. 2694–700, https://doi.org/10.3168/jds.2013-6923.
- ^
As noted previously, standards for animal welfare are generally higher in the EU than elsewhere in the EU. So, as we did with pigs, we’re going to focus on how cows are treated in the EU — but keep in mind that standards in the rest of the world are likely much worse.The EU represents something like the best case for how almost all cows are treated.
The European Food Safety Authority report on the welfare of dairy cows (Nielsen et al., 2023), notes:
Due to climatic conditions and/or limited availability of pasture, year-round access to pasture is not achievable in most EU countries (Reijs et al., 2013). Exceptions are the Portuguese Azores Islands, with a mild climate all year round (de Almeida et al., 2021), and Ireland, though with a lower proportion of farms. Common in Ireland, however, are pasture-based systems with grazing periods over a large part of the year and shorter periods of winter indoor housing (Crossley et al., 2021).
…The most prevalent housing systems in the EU are cubicle housing systems, followed by open-bedded systems and tie-stalls. The proportion of farms offering access to pasture has declined in several EU MSs in the last decades, with an increasing number of farms converting to zero-grazing systems.
Cows are often kept tethered, either permanently or at least the during winter, in ‘tie-stall’ systems (Nielsen et al., 2023):
Worldwide, tie-stall systems have been the predominant type of housing for dairy cows for decades (EFSA AHAW Panel, 2009a,b). In 2008, the proportion of cows tethered at least temporarily during winter in Europe was estimated to be between 20% in the lowlands and 80% in higher, marginal regions (Veissier et al., 2008).
…In tie-stall systems, animals are tethered while in the barn; however, a distinction can be made between (a) permanent tethering (all year round) and (b) tethering during the winter period combined with a varying degree of access to pasture during the summer (review in Beaver et al., 2021).
…In conventional dairy farming, apart from the general requirements in Council Directive 98/58/EC, there are no specific legal EU regulations/restrictions on tethering, except in individual countries, such as Sweden, where access to pasture must be provided during the summer (Loberg et al., 2004), and where construction of new buildings to tether cows has been prohibited since 2007 (Lundmark Hedman et al., 2018). In Denmark, only tie-stall systems built before 2010 may currently be used.11 A Danish ban on tethering will come into force in 2027 and until then grazing is mandatory in summer in tethered herds (review in Beaver et al., 2021). In Austria,12 permanent tethering is not permitted, but with exemptions in terms of lack of space for loafing areas or safety concerns.
Tethering has important welfare implications (Nielsen et al., 2023):
Important welfare implications of tethering compared to loose housing arise from the restricted freedom of movement (Veissier et al., 2008), which can be associated with an increased prevalence of locomotory disorders (Bielfeldt et al., 2005; Mattiello et al., 2005; Kara et al., 2011; Bouffard et al., 2017), as well as an inability to lie or rest comfortably (Haley et al., 2000; Ostojić Andrić et al., 2011; Popescu et al., 2014), an inability to perform comfort and social behaviour (review in Beaver et al., 2021) and an inability to perform oestrus behaviour. In addition, tethering restricts typical calving behaviour as well as early maternal behaviour.
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose, et al. “Welfare of Dairy Cows.” EFSA Journal, vol. 21, no. 5, 1 May 2023, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2023.7993.
- ^
Greenwood, 2021, conducted a review of beef production. Greenwood was a researcher at the Armidale Livestock Industries Centre in New South Wales. He notes:
Beef industries in Europe, New Zealand and India rely heavily on their substantial dairy industries for beef and veal production. Most cow-calf operations within major advanced beef producing regions and countries are pasture-based. South America and Australia have pasture-based systems for growing cattle and finish a substantial proportion of cattle and use pasture for a considerable proportion of cattle for slaughter. North American production systems include a higher proportion of cattle that are feedlot finished for slaughter, although feedlot finishing is increasing in Australia and major South American beef producing nations. … [In Argentina,] feedlot finishing accounted for 28% of cattle slaughtered in 2016 (MLA, 2018a).
…Efficiencies of feedlot production and target market dictate the genotypes of cattle preferred for feedlot finishing. Higher yielding cattle that may be bred from high-yielding terminal-sire European breeds are favoured for efficient, leaner beef production using shorter feedlot finishing periods (≤100 days) to improve consistency of eating quality. Higher-value markets that demand highly marbled beef including export markets to Japan and South Korea require longer-feedlotting periods (100 to ≥350 days, including up to 600 days).
Greenwood, Paul. “Review: An Overview of Beef Production from Pasture and Feedlot Globally, as Demand for Beef and the Need for Sustainable Practices Increase.” Animal, vol. 15, no. 1, 15 July 2021, p. 100295, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.animal.2021.100295.
- ^
According to a scientific opinion from the European Food Safety Authority (Bøtner et al., 2012):
Disbudding means the removal of the horn buds in calves when the actual horn is still absent or very small (< 2 cm), which generally includes animals up to 2 months of age. Only two methods are usually used for disbudding calves – thermocautery (cauterisation with a hot-iron) and chemical cauterisation (caustic paste). The expression dehorning is used for older animals, in which actual horn removal is achieved by means of instruments such as a scoop, embryotomy wire, shears,saws, and others.
On the associated pain (Bøtner et al., 2012):
Dehorning is much more painful that [sic] disbudding. Dehorning, if carried out only under local anaesthesia, will cause severe pain, although this will be slightly delayed in time. Both cautery methods will cause pain for at least 6 hours, but animals disbudded by thermal cautery will struggle more during the procedure. Only nerve blocking with a local anaesthetic associated with a NSAID significantly reduces pain, independently of the method.
On the prevalence of the practice and use of pain relievers (Bøtner et al., 2012):
According to a large European survey carried out in 2008 (ALCASDE, 2009), 40 % of beef farms (which corresponded to approximately 40% of beef cattle) kept bulls without horns. Of this population, 63% were disbudded (52% of these by hot-iron and 48% by caustic paste) and 35% were dehorned. About 2% of the beef cattle population were from polled breeds.
…The ALCASDE (2009) survey showed that anaesthetic or analgesic treatment is administered to the animals prior to or after disbudding in only 35 % of beef cattle. The use of analgesia and sedation increases when dehorning is carried out on older animals (52% of beef), since it is a more invasive procedure and animals are more difficult to restrain. In another European survey it was shown that NSAID were given to 50 % of cows that underwent Caesarean section, 55 % of claw amputations, and in only 1% of dehorning cases (Whay and Huxley, 2005). In another study,1.7 % and 4.6 % of the 605 respondents said they used NSAID after disbudding and castration,respectively.
…A large US survey reported that some dairy owners used an anaesthetic (12.4 %) and analgesia (1.8 %) for dehorning (Fulwider et al.,2008).
…Misch et al. (2007) found that 78 % of dairy producers dehorned their own calves but only 22% used local anaesthetics, and it was also shown that producers who used local anaesthetics were 6.5 times more likely to have veterinary involvement in their dehorning decisions. Horn removal from older cattle was performed with frequent use of drugs and, therefore, it was more consistently carried out by veterinary practitioners, often with the assistance of the stockman.
Bøtner, Anette, et al. “Scientific Opinion on the Welfare of Cattle Kept for Beef Production and the Welfare in Intensive Calf Farming Systems.” EFSA Journal, vol. 10, no. 5, May 2012, p. 2669, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2012.2669.
- ^
The European Food Safety Authority report on the welfare of dairy cows (Nielsen et al., 2023) identified mastitis as a substantial welfare concern:
Mastitis is a disease, characterised by inflammation of the mammary gland (De Vliegher et al., 2018) commonly caused by an intramammary infection (IMI), typically bacterial but less commonly also fungal. The pathogens enter the mammary gland via the teat canal. The condition can be divided in a clinical and a subclinical form, despite there is no respective definition of the two types. Clinical mastitis (CM) is associated with clinical signs, such as abnormal milk and swelling of the mammary gland. It represents a painful condition which results in e.g. reduced eating and lying time, altered laterality of lying or restlessness at milking (Siivonen et al., 2011); severe cases of clinical mastitis may also lead to hyperalgesia (Fitzpatrick et al., 1998). Clinical mastitis is thus considered a substantial welfare problem.
Mastitis is common on dairy farms. According to a systematic review and meta-analysis of hundreds of studies worldwide (Krisnamoorthy et al., 2021):
The pooled prevalence of SCM [subclinical mastitis] and CM [clinical mastitis] were 42% [Confidence Interval (CI) 38-45%, Prediction Interval (PI) 10-83%] and 15% [CI 12-19%, PI 1-81%] in the World respectively.
The European Food Safety Authority report on the welfare of dairy cows also identified locomotor disorders (including lameness) as a major welfare concern (Nielsen et al., 2023):
Foot and leg disorders can be divided into claw disorders such as sole ulcer or white line disease and disorders of the limbs (muscles, joints and skin). They are one of the major welfare issues in dairy cows as these disorders are commonly associated with pain (e.g. Brenninkmeyer et al., 2013; Somers and O’Grady, 2015; Burgstaller et al., 2016; Westin et al., 2016a; Führer et al., 2019). Additionally, they are often associated with restriction of the animals’ ability to perform natural behaviours, such as locomotion and feeding. Foot and leg disorders can be associated with decreasing body condition and an increased risk of concurrent disease (review in Alvergnas et al., 2019; Charlton and Rutter, 2017; Huxley, 2013; Kester et al., 2014; Nuss and Weidmann, 2013; Oehm et al., 2019; Olechnowicz and Jaskowski, 2011; Penev et al., 2012).
Lameness is common across multiple housing systems (Nielsen et al., 2023):
The prevalence of lameness reported from studies of different housing systems varied markedly, both within and between housing systems. For example, Katzenberger et al. (2020) found an average of 7.9% lame cows in tie-stall systems, whereas Oehm et al. (2020), Popescu et al. (2014) and Bouffard et al. (2017) found a substantially higher prevalence of over 20% lame cows using the same scoring system (see Appendix D, Table D.1 for an overview of the literature).
…An evaluation of different studies in cubicle systems also revealed a diverse picture (Appendix D, Table D.2). Sjöström et al. (2018) found the average prevalence of lame cows (moderately and severely lame cows lumped together) ranging from 7% in Sweden to 26% in Germany and France. Using the same scoring system (3-point scoring according to Welfare Quality®, 2009), Gieseke et al. (2020) reported that on average 16% of cows in cubicle systems in Germany were severely lame. The highest prevalence was reported by von Keyserlingk et al. (2012); on average, 55% of cows assessed in each herd in the North-East of the USA were lame (score ≥ 3 in a 5-point system) and 8% were scored severely lame (score ≥ 4). The lowest proportions of lame cows among the studies included in this work (6%) were reported from Algerian small-scale farms (Dendani-Chadi et al., 2020).
…In straw yard systems, the proportion of lame cows (including severely lame ones) ranged from 6% in Spain (Sjöström et al., 2018) to 27% in the UK (Barker et al., 2010) (see Appendix D, Table D.3, for an overview of the literature). This range is approximately comparable to that of studies in compost-bedded pack systems (total lameness prevalence from 4% in the US (score ≥ 3; Lobeck et al., 2011) to 25% in Austria (score ≥ 3; Ofner-Schröck et al., 2015), see Appendix D, Table D.4). For pasture-based systems (data recording in summer), a prevalence of 10% and 12% lame cows have been reported by Crossley et al. (2021) and Somers and O’Grady (2015) (Appendix D, Table D.5).
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose, et al. “Welfare of Dairy Cows.” EFSA Journal, vol. 21, no. 5, 1 May 2023, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2023.7993.
Krishnamoorthy, Paramanandham, et al. “Global and Countrywide Prevalence of Subclinical and Clinical Mastitis in Dairy Cattle and Buffaloes by Systematic Review and Meta-Analysis.” Research in Veterinary Science, vol. 136, May 2021, pp. 561–86, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.rvsc.2021.04.021.
- ^
According to Weschler, 2023:
In intensive beef production in Europe, finishing beef cattle are typically reared in pens with fully slatted floors and low space allowances… The welfare of finishing bulls and steers is at risk if they are housed on fully slatted concrete or wooden floors or not provided with adequate floor space.
According to a scientific opinion from the European Food Safety Authority (Bøtner et al., 2012):
Beef cattle kept on slatted floors have a higher incidence of injuries than animals on straw or sloped, partially straw-bedded areas.
Multiple studies find that slatted floors lead to lameness (for example, Murphy et al., 1975, Murphy et al., 1987, Brscic et al., 2015, Dewell et al., 2018).
Wechsler, B. “Floor Quality and Space Allowance in Intensive Beef Production: A Review.” Animal Welfare, vol. 20, no. 4, Nov. 2011, pp. 497–503, https://doi.org/10.1017/s0962728600003134.
Bøtner, Anette, et al. “Scientific Opinion on the Welfare of Cattle Kept for Beef Production and the Welfare in Intensive Calf Farming Systems.” EFSA Journal, vol. 10, no. 5, May 2012, p. 2669, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2012.2669.
Murphy, PA, et al. “Epiphysitis in Beef Cattle Fattened on Slatted Floors.” PubMed, vol. 97, no. 23, 6 Dec. 1975, pp. 445–7.
Murphy, Peter A, and John Hannan. “Effects of Slatted Flooring on Claw Shape in Intensively Housed Fattening Beef Cattle.” The Bovine Practitioner, 1 Nov. 1987, pp. 133–135, https://doi.org/10.21423/bovine-vol0no22p133-135.
Brscic, M., et al. “Assessment of Welfare of Finishing Beef Cattle Kept on Different Types of Floor after Short- or Long-Term Housing.” Animal, vol. 9, no. 6, 25 Feb. 2015, pp. 1053–1058, [https://doi.org/10.1017/s1751731115000245](https://doi.org/10.1017/s1751731115000245.
Dewell, Reneé D., et al. “Association of Floor Type with Health, Well-Being, and Performance Parameters of Beef Cattle Fed in Indoor Confinement Facilities during the Finishing Phase.” The Bovine Practitioner, American Association of Bovine Practitioners, Feb. 2018, pp. 16–25, https://doi.org/10.21423/bovine-vol52no1p16-25.
- ^
Placzek et al., 2020, conducted a review of separation at birth:
New-born dairy calves are usually permanently separated from their dams within a few hours after birth. This is a typical practice in dairy farming and applies both to organic and conventional production systems (Kälber and Barth 2014). According to the farmers in the study of Wagenaar and Langhout (2007), without early separation, the cows would feed uncontrollable amounts of milk to their calves, which would reduce the amount of produced milk and, consequently, farmers’ income… The reduction of stress is also an argument of the advocates of early cow-calf separation. Supporters of this practice argue that the stress of animals is minimized when the separation takes place before a bond is established between cow and calf (Busch et al. 2017; Ventura et al. 2013).
Both the cows and the calves exhibit behavioral responses after separation that suggest they are experiencing distress (Marchant-Forde et al., 2002):
Early separation in cattle has only received limited attention (Hudson and Mullord, 1977, Kent and Kelly, 1987, Lidfors, 1996, Weary and Chua, 2000, Flower and Weary, 2001) and most of this research has focused on how separation affects the cow, rather than the calf. It has been shown that cows, in particular multiparous cows, find early separation stressful (Phillips, 1993) and that even 24 h after separation cows can still show behavioural signs of distress (Hudson and Mullord, 1977, Kent and Kelly, 1987). However, others report the response to separation being short-lived and mild (Hopster et al., 1995). For the calf, separation prior to natural weaning also appears to evoke increased vocalisation rates, activity and catecholamine concentrations (Lefcourt and Elsasser, 1995; Lidfors, 1996).
Recent studies have investigated the effect of delayed compared to early separation. Some studies conclude that later separation results in more behavioural stress responses in the calves and cows, for example, Flower et al., 2001, find:
The late-separation cows showed a stronger response to separation from the calf than cows separated from calves at less than 1 day after birth. This result corresponds well with earlier studies (Lidfors, 1996; Weary and Chua, 2000) in which separation occurred at the latest 4 days after birth rather than 2 weeks
While others report similar levels of behavioural measures of stress, for example, Mac et al., 2023:
These findings suggest a similar behavioral response to full calf separation and greater occurrence of vocalizations, from cows maintained in a long-term [100 days], pasture-based, cow-calf rearing system when compared to cows separated within 24 h.
Placzek, M., et al. “Public Attitude towards Cow-Calf Separation and Other Common Practices of Calf Rearing in Dairy Farming—a Review.” Organic Agriculture, vol. 11, 8 July 2020, https://doi.org/10.1007/s13165-020-00321-3.
Marchant-Forde, Jeremy N., et al. “Responses of Dairy Cows and Calves to Each Other’s Vocalisations after Early Separation.” Applied Animal Behaviour Science, vol. 78, no. 1, Aug. 2002, pp. 19–28, https://doi.org/10.1016/s0168-1591(02)00082-5. Accessed 30 Jul. 2024.
Flower, Frances C, and Daniel M Weary. “Effects of Early Separation on the Dairy Cow and Calf”: Applied Animal Behaviour Science, vol. 70, no. 4, Jan. 2001, pp. 275–284, https://doi.org/10.1016/s0168-1591(00)00164-7.
Mac, Sarah E, et al. “Behavioral Responses to Cow and Calf Separation: Separation at 1 and 100 Days after Birth.” Animal Bioscience, 14 Nov. 2022, https://doi.org/10.5713/ab.22.0257.
- ^
The British Veterinary Association’s position on surplus male production animals discusses the prevalence of male culling of dairy calves in the UK:
This issue affects large numbers of male dairy calves (bobby calves), which do not have the desired genetic traits for economic meat production and so are often not considered suitable for typical beef rearing. In 2015, 19% of bull calves were killed shortly after birth (approximately 95,000 calves).
We were unable to find rates of culling at birth for other regions, but it’s worth noting that the UK (alongside the EU) tends to have stronger welfare standards than the rest of the world.
- ^
According to the European Food Safety Authority scientific opinion on the welfare of calves (Nielsen et al., 2023):
At ~ 2–5 weeks of age, male calves and some female calves not kept for herd replacement are moved from the dairy farm of origin to auction markets/assembly centres or transported directly to specialised veal units for further fattening (EFSA AHAW Panel, 2022b). Typically, these calves are of Holstein/Friesian breeds, but crossbreds can also be reared as veal calves. In some countries, calves can be, alternatively, fattened in the farm of birth, as it is the case of some herds in France (breeder‐fatteners).
…The diets of calves reared for white veal are restricted in iron to produce meat that is light in colour (hence the name ‘white’ veal) and are comprised mostly of milk replacer, grains and a small amount of roughage (Magrin et al., 2020). Compared with earlier feeding practices, a larger amount of solid feed than what is legally required, has been provided to calves in recent years; however, there is still a tendency to provide solid feed in the form of small particles. Calves are usually fed milk replacer in open troughs or from open buckets without a teat and are not weaned until slaughter. The exact duration of the fattening varies depending on the production country, with France having shorter cycles compared with the Netherlands and Italy (150–175 days vs 190–200 days).
…Compared with white veal, the production of ‘rosé’ veal differs – these calves are weaned off milk at about 3–4 months of age and slaughtered at 8–12 months of age.
…In 2021, ~ 4.08 million white veal calves were slaughtered in the EU‐27 accounting for ~ 620,000 t carcass per year. In addition, ~ 400,000 rosé calves are raised every year (accounting for ~ 76,000 t‐equivalent carcass per year). In 2021, ~ 4.08 million white veal calves were slaughtered in the EU‐27 accounting for ~ 620,000 t carcass per year. In addition, ~ 400,000 rosé calves are raised every year (accounting for ~ 76,000 t‐equivalent carcass per year).
The European Food Safety Authority describes the typical lives of calves raised for veals (Nielsen et al., 2023):
Calves fattened for veal are transported to the veal farm at ~ 14–35 days of age (for details on the impact on welfare of transport of unweaned calves please refer to EFSA AHAW Panel, 2022b). At arrival, calves are placed in individual pens within a large pen, using removable barriers made from tubular metal bars (Figures 5 and and6).6). These individual pens must by law at least be as wide as the height of the calf at the withers and as long as the length of the calf multiplied by 1.1, according to the Council Directive 2008/119/EC. This phase may last between 3 and 6 weeks.
The report identified restriction of movement, isolation stress, inability to perform suckling behaviour, inability to perform play and exploratory behaviour, prolonged hunger, resting problems, gastroenteric disorders, respiratory disorders, as welfare concerns during this stage.
Following the individual pen stage (Nielsen et al., 2023):
Calves are released into group pens holding typically 5–7 calves, but in some instances up to 10 animals are kept together. In group pens, full social contact with pen mates is possible. Calves are kept in this system from 4–7 weeks of age until slaughter at 21–28 weeks. In France, holdings tend to have shorter cycles (160–165 days) in France compared with Italy, Germany and the Netherlands (190–200 days). Calves reared for veal are typically provided with the minimum EU space allowance per animal (i.e. 1.8 m2 per calf) and housed on slatted floors made of wood or very rarely concrete, though rubber flooring on top of wooden or concrete slats is also used on some farms. No enrichment is provided.
Outside of the EU, conditions are much worse, but have recently seen some improvement (Creusinger et al. 2021):
Housing at calf raising facilities, particularly within the veal industry, has been criticized by the public [e.g., (47)] and animal welfare groups. It is commonplace to house calves individually with limited space for the first 8 weeks following arrival to calf raisers. Individual housing of calves is used [as] a biosecurity measure to prevent respiratory disease [reviewed by (48)], which is a leading cause of morbidity and mortality in veal calves (49). However, the potential health benefits of individual housing are inconclusive as prolonged individual housing in veal facilities (>4 weeks) is a risk factor for nasal discharge and coughing (50). Furthermore, individual housing profoundly limits calves’ ability to perform natural behaviors, such as play or social grooming (51, 52). Overall, housing calves in social isolation negatively impacts their physiology, behavior, and welfare [reviewed by (48)] likely due to the lack of both physical and social stimulation. A lack of stimulation may result in boredom and lead to the development of abnormal behaviors (53). In addition to socially restricted housing environment, access to the outdoors or pasture, under most circumstances, is not provided.
…In some parts of the U.S. and Canada, public scrutiny has resulted in regulation and policies that impact how calves are housed and raised. For example, group housing after weaning and increased space allowance per calf is required in Canada and by the Veal Quality Assurance program in the U.S., as well as specific state legislation. For example, veal calves raised in California must have enough room to stand up, lie down, fully extend their limbs, and turn around freely.
We’d guess that conditions outside North America and the EU tend to be similar to those in the US without state-specific legislation, but we haven’t investigated this guess.
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose, et al. “Welfare of Calves.” EFSA Journal, vol. 21, no. 3, Mar. 2023, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2023.7896.
Creutzinger, Katherine, et al. “Perspectives on the Management of Surplus Dairy Calves in the United States and Canada.” Frontiers in Veterinary Science, vol. 8, 13 Apr. 2021, https://doi.org/10.3389/fvets.2021.661453.
- ^
The European Food Safety Authority report on the welfare of cattle during transport (Nielsen et al., 2022):
In total, 11 welfare consequences were identified as being highly relevant for the welfare of cattle during transport based on severity, duration and frequency of occurrence. These were (i) group stress, (ii) handling stress, (iii) heat stress, (iv) injuries, (v) motion stress, (vi) prolonged hunger, (vii) prolonged thirst, (viii) respiratory disorders, (ix) restriction of movement, (x) resting problems and (xi) sensory overstimulation. The occurrence of each type of welfare consequence varied depending on the stage and means of transport.
…In Europe, the current dairy cow population has been estimated to be approximately 23 million animals (Augère-Granier, 2018). Overall, the annual culling rate is 25–30% (Nor et al., 2014). This means, that annually at least 5 million dairy cows are transported to slaughter by road (Figure 15).
…As most cull dairy cows are not in prime condition, there are additional challenges faced by cull dairy cows that are more severe than those experienced by many beef cattle, and the animals will often be less able to cope with the stressors associated with transport (Cockram, 2021) than the average animal.
The European Food Safety Authority report on the welfare of cattle at slaughter gives additional detail (Nielsen et al., 2020).
During transport, cattle are at risk of heat and cold stress, prolonged thirst, prolonged hunger, and fatigue:
During transport, before arriving at slaughter, animals may face very adverse climatic conditions. A Canadian study on 6,152 long journeys from Alberta to the US showed that ambient temperatures across all journeys ranged from –42 to 45°C with a mean value of 18 ± 11.8°C, while temperature variation within a journey was from 0 to 46°C with a mean value of 15 ± 6.6°C (González et al., 2012).
…In very large countries such as Australia (Fisher et al., 2009) or Canada (Gonzales et al., 2012), transport duration and water deprivation for 30 h or 48 h have been reported. Hogan et al., 2007 estimated that in Australia cattle are frequently subjected to feed and water deprivation for about 12 h before, and then during transport in order to reduce digesta load in the gastrointestinal tract. In the latter study, food and water deprivation was associated with some stress indicated by increased levels of plasma cortisol that may be partly responsible for an observed increase in the output of water and nitrogen in urine and faeces.
In certain parts of the world, fasting in cattle can start a few days before transport (Warriss et al., 1990), since it takes time to empty the digestive tract in ruminants, but this is not a common practice worldwide. Smith et al. (1982) in Australia made an experiment on 144 steers fasting them 53 h pre-slaughter and submitting them to 0, 3 or 12 h of road transportation. The mean rate of live weight loss declined progressively with fasting time, from 2.57 kg/h during the first 5.3 h to 0.71 kg/h during the final 23.6 h, meaning that live weight is mainly decreasing at the beginning of fasting, when the digestive tract is emptying. Over the first 18–24 h of transport, loss of bodyweight can reach up to 11%. Animals that lost more than 10% of their bodyweight during transport had a greater likelihood of dying or becoming non-ambulatory or lame (González et al., 2012) thus indicating a compromised welfare.
Long waiting times upon arrival before unloading continue the welfare consequences of transport. In addition, long-waiting times can result in aggressive interactions between cattle:
During transport, cattle usually try to maintain their balance standing up while the vehicle is moving. When the vehicle is stationary, for example at arrival, the animals may start moving (Knowles, 1999), and it is very likely that aggressive interactions would be detrimental to welfare if the cattle are mixed groups of bulls, or cows and heifers in oestrus (Kenny and Tarrant, 1987a,b).
…In an observational survey in a French slaughterhouse during two periods of 5 days (Bourguet et al., 2010), the average time between arrival and unloading was 5.6 ± 0.9 min. Other cattle transport surveys reported by Faucitano and Perdenera (2016) revealed average waiting times between arrival and unloading of 20–30 min, with maximum waiting time ranging from 3 h to overnight. Indeed, in a study of González et al. (2012) in cattle transported for long hauls (> 400 km) from Alberta (Canada) to the US, out of 6,152 journeys studied 82.5% of trucks were not unloaded immediately with a mean unloading delay of 39 min and a maximum of 12 h.
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose, et al. “Welfare of Cattle during Transport.” EFSA Journal, vol. 20, no. 9, 7 Sept. 2022, p. e07442, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2022.7442.
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose, et al. “Welfare of Cattle at Slaughter.” EFSA Journal, vol. 18, no. 11, Nov. 2020, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2020.6275.
- ^
The European Food Safety Authority summarises the welfare concerns at all stages of the slaughter process for cattle in their report on the welfare of cattle at slaughter (Nielsen et al., 2020).
During unloading:
It is considered inappropriate handling causing fear and/or pain when staff move single animals since cattle are gregarious; force the cattle to get off from the truck too quickly or through non-adapted bridges and raceways; or use the wrong material (e.g. goads instead of flags). The use of electric goads causes pain and leads to aversion (Pajor et al., 2000) and is considered a serious welfare concern. Inappropriate handling might cause animals rushing and getting scared and then slipping and falling during unloading. If animals are running, they are more likely to slip and fall (Sandstrom, 2009). It may also lead to animals being reluctant to move, freezing or turning back which in turn may provoke using force and harsh methods (e.g. with electric goads).
Lairage (i.e. holding pens prior to slaughter) can lead to social stress, fear and pain due to unexpected loud noises, thermal stress :
Conflict with pen mates as well the inability for subordinate animals to escape the dominant ones can lead to fear. In case of social stress, animals can be bruised, injured and suffer from pain. Continuous fights can lead to resting problems within the group and fatigue.
…Steers, heifers and anoestrous cows are not aggressive in lairage. Bulls on the other hand need to be managed carefully. Young bulls in a familiar group exhibit play mounting, whereas in mixed groups the interaction between them is of agonistic nature, including butting, mounting, pushing and chasing others. These behaviours can continue for up to 12 h and even in the darkness at night (Kenny and Tarrant, 1987a,b). Owing to this, young bulls in a mixed group are prone to pain, fear and fatigue.
…Noise levels in a slaughterhouse, especially in lairages where metallic gates and ventilation fans are used and pressure washing equipment may be operated, can have a significant effect on the welfare of cattle (Grandin, 1998b). In an exhausted individual, the compensatory mechanisms are more vulnerable than in a rested individual (Brouček, 2014). Thresholds for discomfort for cattle was noted at 90–100 dB, with physical damage to the ear occurring at 110 dB (Phillips, 2009).
…Dairy breeds are more sensitive to noise than beef breeds (Lanier et al., 2000). Weeks et al. (2009) measured the average noise value during the 24 hr in 34 abattoirs in England and Wales and recorded values from 52 to 79 dB for cattle lairages. Iulietto et al. (2018) used a mobile phone app to record noise levels in cattle lairages in three Italian slaughterhouses and reported a range of average values of 56–101 dB.
Loading for stunning:
The movement from the lairage pen to the stunning area constitutes one of the key points regarding animal welfare in abattoirs. Handling and moving of cattle from lairage pens to the restraint should be done calmly and without the use of force by a person. In abattoirs with high slaughter throughput, most of the time animals are forced to move quickly during the last meters prior to stunning to maintain the throughput rate.
…Many stunning boxes have design faults that contribute to levels of distress in cattle (FAWC, 2003). Stepped or sloped floor surfaces are built to assist with roll-out of unconscious cattle from the stun box, which may cause animals to panic.
Stunning methods:
Mechanical stunning methods: Mechanical stunning methods induce brain concussion resulting in unconsciousness through the impact of a penetrative captive bolt, a non-penetrative captive bolt, or free projectiles on the skull of the animal.
…Electrical stunning methods: The principle of electrical stunning is the application of sufficient current through the brain to induce generalised epileptiform activity in the brain, so that the animal becomes immediately unconscious (head-only electrical stunning, Section 3.2.1.5). Head-only electrical stunning can be performed in combination with or immediately followed by passing an electrical current through the body to generate fibrillation of the heart or cardiac arrest (head-to-body electrical stunning, Section 3.2.5.2).
…[During stunning], cattle might experience pain and fear during restraint. Pain and fear can also be caused by ineffective stunning, which will lead to persistence of consciousness during hoisting, sticking and bleeding. Furthermore, recovery of consciousness might occur in effectively stunned animals if sticking was delayed or was not properly done.
…To prevent pain, mechanical restraint should suit the size of the animal. Most of the restraints used in cattle slaughterhouses are not adjustable.
…Penetrative captive bolt powered by cartridge or compressed air is the most commonly used method to stun cattle. Death may occur depending on the degree of injury to the brain but is not a guaranteed outcome (Lambooij and Algers, 2016). Therefore, captive bolt stunning shall be followed as quickly as possible by bleeding or destruction of the brain and upper spinal cord by pithing.
Stunning failures:
Fries et al. (2012) investigated the efficacy of captive bolt stunning in two cattle head deboning slaughterhouses, where a total of 8,879 cattle skulls were investigated for number and precision of shots. Overall, 64.7% of the skulls in slaughterhouse 1 and 65.3% in slaughterhouse 2 were shot in the ideal position and direction. A medium precision (i.e. shots within a range of a maximum distance of 3.0 to 4.5 cm from the crossing point and/or a maximum deviation of 10° to 20° from the vertical direction) was observed in 31.3% and 31.5% of cases, while 4.0% and 3.1% of the skulls indicated a poor precision. In both plants, skulls with more than one shot hole were observed.
Slaughter:
Exsanguination of cattle immediately following stunning is an important step in the slaughter process intended to [cause] death in unconscious animals. Under commercial slaughter situations, cattle are bled out with a chest stick (referred to as sticking) aimed at severing the brachiocephalic trunk which gives rise to the carotid arteries and vertebral artery supplying oxygenated blood to the brain (EFSA, 2004; HSA, 2016a,b).
…The presence of consciousness at sticking or cutting, or recovery of consciousness during bleeding, is a serious animal welfare concern for at least two reasons. First, the incision made in the neck and chest sticking involves substantial tissue damage in areas well supplied with nociceptors (Kavaliers, 1988). The activation of the protective nociceptive system induces the animal to experience pain. Second, onset of death due to sticking is not immediate, and there is a period of time during which the animal may regain consciousness and then experience pain, fear and distress (EFSA AHAW Panel, 2013).
…In effectively stunned cattle, sticking should be performed as soon as possible. In any case a maximum stun-to-stick interval of 60 seconds for the penetrative captive-bolt and 30 seconds for the non-penetrative captive-bolt have been suggested (HSA, 2016a,b). In commercial slaughterhouses, sticking of cattle may be performed after captive bolt stunning, which is most commonly used, following shackling and hoisting the unconscious animals and moving it on an overhead rail to the bleeding area. Owing to this, there would be a delay between the end of stunning and sticking.
…Cattle with signs of life undergoing dressing may recover consciousness and consequently experience pain, fear and distress. Lack of skilled operators, short bleeding time, incomplete sectioning of the brachiocephalic trunk or carotid arteries, occlusion of carotids (false aneurisms) and lack of monitoring of death before dressing begins are hazard origins.
Slaughter without stunning:
When slaughtered without stunning, cattle are killed through exsanguination by severing all the soft tissues, including blood vessels, in the neck usually at the level of second to fourth cervical vertebrae (EFSA, 2004; von Holleben et al., 2010).
…Cattle are either restrained in an upright, rotated or inverted position. For example, in Europe, from the 2.1 million animals slaughtered without stunning, more than 1.6 million (78%) are slaughtered in a rotating device, while the rest (22%) are slaughtered in an upright device…
…The presence of consciousness during slaughter without stunning causes severe welfare consequences. First, the incision made in the neck and chest sticking involves substantial tissue damage in areas well supplied with nociceptors (Kavaliers, 1988). The activation of the protective nociceptive system induces the animal to experience pain. Second, onset of death due to sticking is not immediate, and there is a period of time during which the animal remains conscious and experiences pain, fear and distress (EFSA AHAW Panel, 2013).
Nielsen, Søren Saxmose, et al. “Welfare of Cattle at Slaughter.” EFSA Journal, vol. 18, no. 11, Nov. 2020, https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2020.6275.
- ^
Both castration and tail docking are allowed to be performed on sheep without analgesics or anaesthesia before a certain age, usually seven days old for tail docking of lambs and six weeks to three months for castration (some methods always require pain relief) in most parts of the world.
Madeleine, et al., discuss tail docking around the world:
Docking the tails of sheep is a very common animal husbandry practice, particularly in countries that manage sheep in extensive systems such as Australia… The prevention of flystrike (cutaneous myiasis) and breech cleanliness are the primary reasons producers dock sheep tails in Australia and around the world. Flystrike is a significant welfare issue and an Australian priority endemic disease, costing the industry AUD 300 million in treatment, prevention, and production losses annually. (Woodruff et al., 2023)
According to a report into castration and tail docking in lambs by the UK Government’s Animal Welfare Committee:
The evidence presented by the industry indicates that castration is usually carried out using the rubber ring method without anaesthesia or analgesia. Other options for castration include short scrotum castration, clamp castration and the combined method, although the evidence suggests that these are less widely used than rubber rings. Tail docking may also be carried out using the rubber ring method, or with a sharp knife, using a hot iron that cauterises the wound, or with a clamp (e.g., Burdizzo), generally combined with a rubber ring. As with castration, the most common method is the rubber ring on young lambs without anaesthesia or analgesia.
On the use of anaesthesia, the report notes:
…In 2008, FAWC recommended that pain relief (anaesthetics and analgesics) should be used for both castration and tail docking whenever possible, and that research should be directed towards the development of practical methods for delivering pain relief under farming conditions and for different ages of lambs.
Industry evidence suggests that pain relief is rarely used for either castration or tail docking. There are several likely reasons for this. There is no legal requirement to use anaesthetics on lambs that are castrated or tail docked using a rubber ring within their first 7 days of life. However, as noted above, anecdotal evidence suggests that these practices are often carried out after the 7-day legal limit for using rubber rings (or, in Scotland, for using rubber rings without anaesthetic).
A more probable explanation is that use of anaesthetics would be an additional stage in the process, thus adding stress for the lamb, and extra time and cost for the farmer during the very busy lambing period. Farmers may not identify signs of pain or discomfort or may choose to overlook these and may well lack the skills required to administer a local anaesthetic by injection in a consistently hygienic and effective way.
The 2008 FAWC (UK Government Farm Animal Welfare Committee) report referenced in the first line described the causes of pain in detail:
Elastration is probably the most widely used method of tail docking. The ring prevents
blood flow to the distal tissues, which atrophy and drop off after 4 to 6 weeks. The method is
quick, easy, and reliably effective, but has been shown to cause acute pain and stress in lambs at all ages investigated including lambs of less than one week of age, for which its use without anaesthesia is restricted by law in the UK. Although there